Jump to content

Universal causation: Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
minor edit
Russell's view
Line 5: Line 5:
or
or
Causality is universal. Nowhere in the world can there be any phenomena that do not give rise to certain consequences and have not been caused by other phenomena. — [[Alexander Spirkin]] in "Dialectical Materialism", 1984}}
Causality is universal. Nowhere in the world can there be any phenomena that do not give rise to certain consequences and have not been caused by other phenomena. — [[Alexander Spirkin]] in "Dialectical Materialism", 1984}}

In contrast [[Bertrand Russell]] points out that the law of causation as usually stated by philosophers is false and is not used in sciences (maybe with exception to their infancy).<ref>Russell, B. (1912). On the Notion of Cause. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 13, new series, 1-26. Retrieved August 16, 2020, from www.jstor.org/stable/4543833</ref>



==As axioms of causality==
==As axioms of causality==

Revision as of 20:42, 16 August 2020

Universal Causation is the proposition that everything in the universe has a cause and is thus an effect of that cause. This means that if a given event occurs, then this is the result of a previous, related event.[1] If an object is in a certain state, then it is in that state as a result of another object interacting with it previously.

The idea of universal causation is formulated similarly in western philosophy for ages, however the formulations have some profound differences in methodology and philosophical assumptions.

Examples of formulation:

In addition, everything that becomes or changes must do so owing to some cause; for nothing can come to be without a cause. — Plato in "Timaeus", c. 360 BC

or

Causality is universal. Nowhere in the world can there be any phenomena that do not give rise to certain consequences and have not been caused by other phenomena. — Alexander Spirkin in "Dialectical Materialism", 1984

In contrast Bertrand Russell points out that the law of causation as usually stated by philosophers is false and is not used in sciences (maybe with exception to their infancy).[2]


As axioms of causality

According to William Whewell (hypothetico-deductivist view) the concept of universal causation depends on three axioms:[3]

  1. Nothing takes place without a cause
  2. The magnitude of an effect is proportional to the magnitude of its cause
  3. To every action there is an equal and opposed reaction.

Whewell writes that the first axiom is so clear that it requires no proof.[4]

Example

Example for the axiom: if a baseball is moving through the air, it must be moving this way because of a previous interaction with another object, such as being hit by a baseball bat.

Criticism

An epistemological axiom is a self-evident truth. Thus the "Axiom of Causality" claims to be a universal rule that is so obvious that it does not need to be proved to be accepted. Even among epistemologists, the existence of such a rule is controversial. See the full article on Epistemology.

As Law of Universal Causation or Principle of Universal Causation (PUC)

John Stuart Mill describes the Law of Universal Causation in following way:

Every phenomenon has a cause, which it invariably follows; and from this are derived other invariable sequences among the successive stages of the same effect, as well as between the effects resulting from causes which invariably succeed one another.[5]

Contrary to hypothetico-deductivists Mill focuses on inductive reasoning and senses in framing of the Law of Universal Causation i.e. uses basic features of experimental methods and convinces, after critical analysis, that this law is proved by induction better then any other of subordinate generalizations.[6][7]

the belief we entertain in the universality, throughout nature, of the law of cause and effect, is itself an instance of induction[6]

Also popular proof and answer to skepticism (for instance that of David Hume's) is that PUC has been true in so many cases, that (using basic scientific method enumerative inductive reasoning)[7] it is reasonable to say that it is true in every case, moreover counter-example i.e. event that does not have a cause is hard to conceive.[8]

Criticism

Modern version of law of universal causation is connected with Newtonian physics, but is also criticized for instance by David Hume who presents skeptical reductionist view on causality.[9] Since then his view on the concept of causality is often predominating (see Causality, After the Middle Ages). Kant answered to Hume in many aspects, defending the a priority of universal causation.[10]

Spontaneity

One implication of Universal Causation is that if a phenomenon appears to occur without any observable external cause, the cause must be internal. See Compatibilism.

Variation

Another implication of the Universal Causation is that all change in the universe is a result of the continual application of physical laws.

Determinism

If all events are cause and effect relationships that follow universal rules, then all events—past, present and future—are theoretically determinate. See Causal determinism.

First Cause

If all effects are the result of previous causes, then the cause of a given effect must itself be the effect of a previous cause, which itself is the effect of a previous cause, and so on, forming an infinite logical chain of events that can have no beginning.

Exception for the Universal Causation - First Cause is sometimes pointed out to be logically necessary for it to not contradict itself. Infinite chain of events is hard to conceive in finite world. The answer is looped chain of events. But this is also questioned as the whole loop would have no cause. However it can not be ruled out that the Universe is infinite in time.

See also

References

  1. ^ "Law of universal causation", Webster's Revised Unabridged Dictionary (editor Noah Porter, Springfield, MA: C. & G. Merriam Co., 1913)
  2. ^ Russell, B. (1912). On the Notion of Cause. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 13, new series, 1-26. Retrieved August 16, 2020, from www.jstor.org/stable/4543833
  3. ^ Losee, John. Theories of Causality: From Antiquity to the Present. p. 129.
  4. ^ William Whewell, (1840). The Philosophy of the Inductive Sciences Founded Upon Their History, p. 171.
  5. ^ System of Logic 1872, Book III p.112
  6. ^ a b System of Logic 1872, Book III, Chapter V, Of The Law Of Universal Causation., pp. 373-426, Chapter XXI, Of The Evidence Of The Law Of Universal Causation, pp. 95-111
  7. ^ a b https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/scientific-method/#HisRevAriMil
  8. ^ Castell, A. (1972). The Status of the Principle of Universal Causation. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 32(3), 403-407. doi:10.2307/2105573
  9. ^ James Baillie, "Routledge Philosophy GuideBook to Hume on Morality"
  10. ^ https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/kant-hume-causality/