Thinking as a subversive activity: doing philosophy in the
corporate universitynup_551 28..37
Gary Rolfe PhD Professor of Nursing, College of Human and Health Sciences, Swansea University, Swansea, UK Abstract The academy is in a mess. The cultural theorist Bill Readings claimed that it is in ruins, while the political scientist Michael Oakeshott sug- gested that it has all but ceased to exist. At the very least, we might argue that the current nancial squeeze has distorted the University into a shape that would be all but unrecognizable to Oakeshott and others writing in the 1950s and 1960s. I will begin this paper by tracing the development of the modern Enlightenment University over the past 200 years from its roots in late 18th century Berlin to its current predica- ment. I will then turn my attention to the introduction during the 1990s of nursing education into the University, and examine the particular difculties and tensions encountered at the interface between a profes- sional practice and an academic discipline. Finally, I will propose phi- losophy as a way of dwelling in the ruins of the Enlightenment University and of reconciling the corporate demands of the University with the obligations of the nursing profession. Keywords: education programme, nursing philosophy. The University in ruins It is generally agreed that the origins of the modern Enlightenment University can be found in the writ- ings of the German thinkers Wilhelm von Humboldt and Immanuel Kant, whose ideas led to the founding of the University of Berlin in 1810. Kant (1798) argued that the University should ostensibly be accountable to the state, but ultimately to the prin- ciples of truth and reason, while von Humboldt (1810) emphasized the role of the University in developing the moral culture of the nation and of the individual. This model of the pursuit of knowledge for primarily moral and cultural ends spread rapidly across Western Europe and, by the middle of the 19th century, John Henry Newman (1858) was describing the ideal of the gentleman scholar who, with his broad classical edu- cation, was morally and practically equipped for any profession or walk of life. The idea of the Enlighten- ment University as a community of scholars in pursuit of a unied and universally applicable body of Correspondence: Professor Gary Rolfe, Professor of Nursing, College of Human and Health Sciences, Swansea University, Singleton Park, Swansea SA2 8PP, UK. Tel.: +44 (0)1792 295809; fax: +44 (0)1792 295487; e-mail: [email protected] O r i g i n a l a r t i c l e 28 2012 Blackwell Publishing Ltd Nursing Philosophy (2013), 14, pp. 2837 knowledge for its own sake persisted well into the 20th century, where it nally came under pressure from what was by now a fully industrialized state to produce engineers, technicians, and scientists with specic skill-sets, and for whom the classics had little relevance or meaning. As a result of the pressure exerted by governments for universities to make a more substantive and practical contribution to the workforce, many degrees in pure subjects such as philosophy began to disappear, to be replaced by qualications in applied or professional subjects such as teaching and nursing. The University of Culture and the crisis of legitimation In his book The University in Ruins, Bill Readings (1996) argued that the original moral and cultural function of the Enlightenment University was closely linked to the development and specic identity of individual emerging nation states, and what he referred to as the University of Culture therefore played a vital unifying role by articulating and dis- seminating the cultural norms and values distinct to each of the nations of Western Europe and North America. In return, the government funded the uni- versity sector and was prepared to allow it a certain degree of academic freedom, provided of course that the University continued to uphold and promote the values and cultural norms of the state. However, Readings identied two developments during the second half of the 20th century which fatally fractured this symbiotic relationship between University and State. Firstly, our ideas of culture began to fragment. The culture wars of the 1950s and 1960s highlighted the growing divide between the arts and the sciences, for example in the public and acri- monious falling-out between F.R. Leavis and C.P. Snow. This was compounded in the 1960s by the breaking down of the barriers between so-called high and low (or popular) culture, to the extent that the term culture became more or less meaningless. Sec- ondly, the growth of internationalism and the global village blurred national identities and cultural stereo- types, leading Readings to observe that: the nation state and the modern notion of culture arose together, and they are I argue, ceasing to be essential to an increasingly transnational global economy. (Readings, 1996, p. 12) The very raison detre of Readingss University of Culture was therefore under threat, resulting in what he referred to as a crisis of legitimation for the University. One of the effects of this calling into question of the purpose of the University has been a re-evaluation of how and why it is funded. The original moral and cultural missions of the University had clear benets to the state, which was prepared to pay for what was a largely non-productive institution. However, as the mission of the University shifted during the latter part of the 20th century from providing a broad education to awarding work-based qualications, and as the opportunity to gain those qualications was extended to a greater and greater proportion of the population, it was increasingly expected that the beneciaries of the qualications rather than the state would foot the bill, an expectation that has intensied as a result of the current climate of austerity. In addition, as the University began to make inroads into the profes- sional education and training market, it needed to distinguish itself from other more established provid- ers such as technical colleges. Readings suggested that the University has responded to these challenges in two ways. Firstly, it has wholeheartedly embraced the ethos of the market economy. As he rst pointed out in the early 1990s, the University is not just like a corporation; it is a corporation. Students . . . are not like custom- ers, they are customers (Readings, 1996, p. 22). Whereas the cultural mission of the University was largely cooperative and collaborative, the market economy in which universities now nd themselves pits one against the other and all against the alter- native providers of vocational qualications such as colleges of further education and technical colleges. Of course, the major advantage of universities over other providers is the very fact that they are universities, with all the cachet that the title pro- vides. Secondly then, as Readings observed, excel- lence was promoted as the new selling point, Thinking as a Subversive Activity 29 2012 Blackwell Publishing Ltd Nursing Philosophy (2013), 14, pp. 2837 distinguishing feature and legitimating idea of the University as an institution. However, he further suggested that the term excellence was being used to refer not only to the quality of the product being sold by universities, but to the product itself. In other words, universities were in the business of selling excellence. The University of Excellence At some point during the second half of the 20th century, the University of Culture was replaced by the University of Excellence. We can see this appeal to excellence in the mission statements, public pro- nouncements, and aspirations of many universities, including my own, and Readingss book The Univer- sity in Ruins can be read as an extended critique of the corporate University of Excellence. On the one hand, the idea of the University of Excellence is almost tautological: of course universities should aspire to excellence; that is what they are for. On the other hand, however, Readings points out that the idea of excellence is empty, that it is quite literally meaningless, a signier without a signied. In order to illustrate his point, he offered the example of the estates department at Cornell University in the USA, which was given an award for excellence in parking. It turned out that the award was actually given for the success of the department in preventing staff and students from parking on the campus: for restricting parking rather than for facilitating it. As Readings pointed out, the award could just as readily have been given for attempts either to increase or decrease the number of parking spaces on campus, so that excellence can function equally well as an evaluative criterion on either side of the issue of what constitutes excellence in parking (Readings, 1996, p. 24). For a university to describe itself as excellent therefore tells us nothing about it beyond an aspiration to do well or to be better in some unspecied way than its competitors, all of which are making exactly the same claim. For example, my own university, along with many others, aspires to excellence in research (Swansea University, 2009). As a nurse, I might consider excel- lent research to be work that improves the lives of patients. As a philosopher, I might consider excellent research to be work that helps us to think differently and more productively about particular problems, or to problematize ideas that were previously taken for granted. This is not, however, what the senior aca- demics and administrators in my university mean by excellent research. For them, excellent research is research which is published in journals with a high citation index, which is cited by other researchers, and which is funded by prestigious grant-awarding bodies; that is, research that is likely to make a con- tribution to the universitys score in what used to be called the Research Assessment Exercise in the UK, but which has recently (and perhaps not coinciden- tally) been rebranded as the Research Excellence Framework. However, closer inspection will reveal that the term excellence does not apply to the research at all. The criteria for excellence are concerned with what happens before and after the research takes place, with writing and submitting the grant proposal and with writing up and publishing the ndings. As far as my university managers are concerned, the aim, objectives, and conduct of the study and its applica- tion to the real world are largely irrelevant as mea- sures of excellence. What makes for excellent nursing research is not whether it improves peoples lives, but whether it is funded by a prestigious grant-awarding body and written-up in a top academic journal. Fur- thermore, I have noticed recently that excellent research is no longer being dened by my university simply in terms of the size of the grant, but by the overheads that the awarding body is prepared to pay; that is, by the prot that the university will make. Excellent research is, more and more, research that brings in money to the university. The point that Readings was making is that the term excellent is available to universities to promote whatever happens to be expedient at the time. As the Univer- sity as an institution becomes ever more corporate and money is in ever shorter supply, excellence is being dened more and more in economic terms; as the recession continues to bite, Peter Druckers concept of the knowledge economy is increasingly being interpreted simply as the economic value of knowledge. Gary Rolfe 30 2012 Blackwell Publishing Ltd Nursing Philosophy (2013), 14, pp. 2837 The industrialization of the University The University, then, is in the knowledge business: the business of manufacturing and selling knowledge, information, and qualications on an increasingly industrial scale. As research grants get bigger, research is being carried out by multidisciplinary teams of specialists in narrower and narrower elds of expertise. Projects are passed along what resembles a factory assembly line from methodologist to litera- ture reviewer to economist to ethicist to statistician to eldworker to data analyst and so on, until a com- pleted project report with a dozen or so names on it emerges from the end of the conveyor belt. Similarly, class sizes are getting bigger and more geographically dispersed, sometimes across several continents, and teaching is becoming more technological and less per- sonal. This, incidentally, is often promoted as some- thing positive rather than as a nancial expediency. The concept of education, which includes moral and social components, no longer gures in the mission statement of my university, and has been replaced by learning and teaching and the student experience. Even this is a misnomer, since there is a growing number of courses and modules which include very little teaching in any recognizable form. In order to manage the industrialization of research and teaching, Readings suggested that the academic is being replaced by the administrator, that thought is being replaced by efciency and protability, that quality is being replaced by quan- tity, and that academic accountability is being replaced by nancial accountancy. Thus, the role of the course leader is becoming increasingly manage- rial, the role of the principal investigator of a research project is now largely administrative, and both are being called to account for their successes and failures on nancial rather than academic or scholarly grounds. And, of course, the student is being replaced by the customer who in many cases wishes to purchase a qualication that can be cashed-in in some future workplace rather than an education whose worth is largely intrinsic. We should hardly be surprised by these developments. Writing over 60 years ago, Michael Oakeshott issued the fol- lowing warning: A university will have ceased to exist when its learning has degenerated into what is now called research, when its teaching has become mere instruction and occupies the whole of an undergraduates time, and when those who come to be taught . . . desire only a qualication for earning a living or a certicate to let them in on the exploitation of the world. (Oakeshott, 1950, p. 117) In retrospect, we might argue that some faculties and departments in the University have already met the fate that Oakeshott described, and that nursing is perhaps one of them. The place of nursing in the University Oakeshotts apocalyptic vision of the end of the Uni- versity only really became apparent in the UK in the 1980s with the imposition of the Thatcherite eco- nomic policy of the internal market. As the University became more and more corporate and was increas- ingly governed by consumer-driven market forces, it began to shift its focus and tailor its products away from pure subjects which have traditionally been studied at least in part out of scholarly interest, and towards applied subjects which are taken primarily in order to obtain a qualication that has currency in the workplace. Initially, students gravitated towards the well-established and academically respectable technological disciplines such as engineering, but the 1990s saw the arrival of many new subjects and departments in the University with an overt voca- tional focus, including (among many others) cultural studies, leisure studies, sports studies, business studies, tourism studies, and retail studies. As we can see, this new category of university departments can usually be identied by the word studies in the title, which is appended in order to signify that a pastime, interest, or occupation is now the subject of academic study. These new departments often directly address the requirements of the service industries, and generally consist of a patchwork of modules, topics, and other elements taken from a variety of existing academic subjects, often from the humanities and social sciences. Thinking as a Subversive Activity 31 2012 Blackwell Publishing Ltd Nursing Philosophy (2013), 14, pp. 2837 Nursing in the academy When nurse training courses rst moved en masse into the UK higher education sector in the 1990s, they tended to adopt many of the characteristics of these so-called studies subjects. The Project 2000 curricu- lum at the time emphasized the importance of knowl- edge from the social sciences and encouraged patchwork courses that consisted of sociology, psy- chology, social research, life sciences and, in some cases, philosophy modules, often taught by non- nursing lecturers from other departments. As the aca- demic discipline of nursing matured, it embeddeditself into the University sector and started to develop its own academic staff, theoretical perspectives, research methodologies, and epistemological and ontological positions. It subsequently attemptedtodissociate itself from the overtly practical and usually vocational approach of the studies subjects and assert itself as a fully-edged academic discipline in its own right. However, the development of nursing as an aca- demic subject created a professional, epistemological and often a geographical schism between those who taught nursing and those who practised it. This in turn triggered a number of controversies and disagree- ments about what nurses should be doing and how they should be prepared for their role. The disputes currently being played out in the academic, profes- sional, and popular press include, among others, whether nurse education is too theoretical or too prac- tical; whether it has been dumbed down or over- intellectualized; whether nurses are over-qualied to perform basic nursing care or not bright enough to take onextended(usually medical) roles; whether they should be educated in a university lecture theatre or trained in a hospital ward; whether nursing practice should involve conceptual problem-solving or the technical application of research-based procedures and directives; and whether the relationship of nurses to doctors should be that of handmaiden, assistant, partner, or replacement. That these issues continue to resist our attempts at resolution should alert us to the possibility that there is something amiss, on the one hand in the relationship between academic nursing and the nursing profession, and on the other between academic nursing and the rest of the University. There have been numerous diagnoses of the problem, but they can, on the whole, be boiled down to the simple fact that nurse academics, unlike most of their university colleagues, are being pulled in two often conicting directions. On the one hand, the demands of the corporate University are steering us ever more towards nancially driven goals and out- comes, while on the other hand we also have to take into account a variety of professional demands, for example in the UK, the nursing code of conduct to which all registered nurses, including myself, have signed up (Nursing and Midwifery Council, 2008). As we have seen, the corporate research agenda exerts pressure on us to listen and respond to the needs of research councils and other grant providers rather than to the needs of practitioners and service provid- ers; to choose research projects based on the size and source of the grant rather than on professional crite- ria such as the contribution that the study will make to nursing practice and theory; to conduct large mul- ticentre experimental research projects rather than to engage with practitioners and service users in small- scale local studies that will have a direct impact on professional practice and patient care; and to publish our ndings in journals with high impact factors which are read and cited only by other researchers rather than journals which are read and acted upon by practitioners. Likewise, the corporate learning and teaching agenda emphasizes student throughput, retention and demonstrable outcomes on the one hand, and student experience and customer satisfaction on the other. In some extreme cases, this has resulted in students who are patently unsafe and incompetent being pushed through their courses in the name of economic expediency and being awarded diplomas and degrees that entitle them to practise as qualied nurses. In contrast to this corporate customer- focused strategy, education for professional practice entails far more than the simple and straightforward transmission of generalizable propositional knowl- edge and does not t with the competencies-based, outcome-driven corporate teaching agenda, nor with the high-tech, high-volume, high-throughput distance-learning approach. Neither does it sit com- fortably with the technical rational epistemology of Gary Rolfe 32 2012 Blackwell Publishing Ltd Nursing Philosophy (2013), 14, pp. 2837 practice and the simplistic procedural and pathways- driven approach of the evidence-based nursing movement. In a nutshell, I have suggested that pre-registration nursing education entered the academy at the point when it was turning into a market-driven corporation, and that the values and aims of the nursing profession are becoming ever more at odds with those of the University. As a further complication, the academic discipline of nursing is not readily accommodated in the current university structure: it is not a technology in which research ndings are applied simply and unproblematically to practice; it is not one of the dwindling number of pure subjects; and neither does it t with the growing number of studies, most of which are theoretically underdeveloped and whose coherence and identity is achieved through a patch- work of applied bits and pieces from other disciplines. Furthermore, the University (or, at least, my univer- sity) has no real interest in nursing as an academic discipline beyond its utility as an undergraduate cash cow, and has shown little inclination to listen or respond to its particular needs. The demise of Thought The academic discipline of nursing is faced with a dilemma, perhaps with an aporia. There is no going back, no return to some golden age of the Enlighten- ment University and, at least at the moment, no pros- pect of an exit from the university sector. We must therefore make the best of what we have and of where we nd ourselves, albeit in the face of a general disinterest and often a lack of respect from the wider academic community. Some colleagues have responded by playing down or even abandoning their commitments to the nursing profession, to practitio- ners, and to patients, and have fully and wholeheart- edly embraced the corporate mission of grant capture and student throughput. It might even be argued that this is our only option if we wish to thrive or even to survive in the University. As Lyotard (1979, p. xxiv) remarked, the ethos of the times is be operational or disappear. The challenge for those of us who wish to resist the corporate University from within is therefore to full the basic demand to be operational lest we disappear, while at the same time exploring new and creative ways of making a scholarly contribution to nursing practice and theory. We must, in Bill Readingss words, nd ways of dwelling in the ruins of the Uni- versity without recourse either to romantic nostalgia, cynicism, or despair. There is clearly no single simple recipe for this, and Readings was suitably vague when it came to the practicalities. He was quite clear, however, that the demise of the academy went hand in hand with the rejection of Thought (his capitaliza- tion) as its primary activity and purpose. For Read- ings, then, the University is in ruins primarily because Thought, as an activity of intrinsic worth rather than as a means to some corporate nancial end, is no longer valued or encouraged in either students or academic staff. As Readings pointed out, Thought is non-productive labor, and hence does not show up on balance sheets except as waste (Readings, 1996, p. 175). Thought as an activity of intrinsic worth has lost its pre-eminence in the University, and as we might expect, the devaluation of Thought is inextricably linked to the demise of philosophy as a distinct and unique academic discipline. Thought would appear to offer little to the modern student in search of a voca- tional qualication, and as Readings observed: nothing in the nature of the institution will enshrine Thought or protect it from economic imperatives (Readings, 1996). But if the devaluation of Thought is linked to the demise of the academic discipline of philosophy, then arguably the reinstatement of phi- losophy to the academy will bring with it a renewed commitment to critique and the practice of thinking. Philosophy and the lower faculty The faculty of philosophy originally occupied a special and privileged place within the Enlightenment University, to the extent that the idea of a University without a philosophy department was until recently considered unthinkable. Writing in the late 18th century, Kant categorized the University into three higher faculties and a lower faculty. The purpose of the higher faculties of theology, law, and medicine was to attend, as he put it, to the eternal, civil, and physical well-being of the people, and this task fell largely Thinking as a Subversive Activity 33 2012 Blackwell Publishing Ltd Nursing Philosophy (2013), 14, pp. 2837 under the remit and control of the state. However, in addition to these three state-controlled faculties, Kant argued that: It is absolutely essential that the learned community at the university also contain a faculty that is independent of the governments command with regard to its teachings; one that, having no commands to give, is free to evaluate every- thing, and concerns itself with the interests of the sciences [Wissenschaft], that is, with truth; one in which reason is authorized to speak out publicly. (Kant, 1798, pp. 2729) Kant identied philosophy as the faculty charged with this critical (in both senses of the word) role. He continued: The reason why this faculty, despite its great prerogative (freedom), is called the lower faculty lies in human nature; for a man who can give commands, even though he is someone elses humble servant, is considered more distin- guished than a free man who has no one under his command. (p. 29) From the very outset then, philosophy occupied a unique position in the modern University. Philoso- phers were largely free to think outside of the con- straints of government control and accountability, and performed the essential duty of evaluating and regu- lating the higher faculties. Philosophy acted both as a mediator between the disparate agendas of the facul- ties of divinity, law, and medicine, and also as the critical function that called them to account. It was able to do this because, for Kant (1787, p. 657), phi- losophy is unique among the faculties insofar as it has no content of its own but is rather the science of the relation of all knowledge to the essential ends of human reason. The demise of philosophy The triple role of philosophy as the dening feature of the University, as the mediator between the other faculties, and as the independent and neutral faculty of critique charged with the pursuit of truth, gradually eroded during the early years of the 20th century. On the one hand, the discipline of philosophy began to turn its gaze inward and to call into question its own relationship with truth. And on the other hand, it renounced its neutral position with regard to the other faculties and was perceived to turn away from the arts towards mathematics and science. In the view of Jurgen Habermas (1968, p. 4), philosophy moved from providing a reective and transcendent theory of universal knowledge to what he called the pseudo- normative regulation of established research. This scientic turn, under the guise of logical positivism and later of analytical and linguistic philosophy, resulted in a schism within the university and a back- lash in the form rstly of German phenomenology and latterly of French post-structural philosophy and literary criticism. By the second half of the 20th century, philosophy had become detached from everyday affairs and largely inaccessible to the educated lay person. More worryingly, however, philosophy in the 20th century had become too technical and specialized even for academics from other faculties in the University, so that its function since the time of Kant as the gate- keeper of truth and reason was called into question. Suddenly, the idea of a University without a faculty of philosophy was no longer quite so unthinkable. As philosophy departments in the UK began to close, there was a rapid diaspora of philosophers across the whole university as they found new homes in depart- ments as diverse as medicine, geography, cultural studies, and English literature. A number of writers have expressed concern over this apparent resur- gence of philosophy across the University. Alain Badiou, writing in 2009, complained that: if philosophys existence was declared minimal twenty years ago, one could today maintain that it nds itself no less under threat but for the diametrically opposed reason that it is now endowed with an excessive, articial existence. Particularly in France, philosophy is everywhere. It serves as a trade- mark for various media pundits. It livens up cafs and health clubs. It has its magazines and its gurus. It is universally called upon, by everything from banks to major state com- missions, to pronounce on ethics, law and duty. (Badiou, 2009, pp. 6768) Elsewhere, Badiou (2005) made the distinction between the TV philosopher who is wheeled out to give an opinion on the issues of the day, and the Gary Rolfe 34 2012 Blackwell Publishing Ltd Nursing Philosophy (2013), 14, pp. 2837 genuine philosopher who constructs her/his own problems rather than merely resolving the problems of others. If we apply Badious distinction to the academy, we can see that there is a danger that the applied phi- losophers who are found in departments across the University, including nursing, are becoming little more than the TV variety who pronounce on the ethics of this or the epistemology of that, and whose role is to answer questions rather than to pose them. This fundamental shift in what the academy now demands of philosophy and philosophers might be seen as a response to the growing ethos of manageri- alism in the corporate University. As one manager in my own department was recently overheard to say to an academic: Dont bring me problems, bring me solutions. As corny and clichd as that remark might sound, it ts perfectly with the growing corporate culture of measurable outcomes, key performance indicators, and tangible (preferably monetary) results. The role of the philosopher (and, indeed, of all aca- demics) is no longer to problematize but to provide simplied answers to simplistic questions. The Univer- sity has, to use Michael Oakeshotts phrase, ceased to function as a manner of human activity and has become a machine for achieving a particular purpose or producing a particular result. Thus, while many so-called multidisciplinary teams and departments now employ a philosopher, there is an expectation that everyone pulls together in order to reach a con- sensus and produce a result, and that the role of the philosopher is to solve her/his particular aspect of the problem at hand as it rolls along the conveyor belt. The return of philosophy This expectation that the philosopher will t seam- lessly into the team, will bring a philosophical point of view to the table, and will resolve problems through reasoned discussion and the application of logic is based on what is arguably a naive misconcep- tion about philosophy and philosophers. Slavoj iek (2005) suggests how a true philosopher might be recognized: Youre sitting in a caf and someone challenges you: Come on, lets discuss that in depth. The philosopher will immedi- ately say Im sorry, I must leave, and will make sure he disappears as quickly as possible. (p. 49) Philosophers, then, tend not to be team players and are not concerned with simple or simplistic solutions. iek (echoing Wittgenstein) continued: Philosophy is not a dialogue. Name me a single example of a successful philosophical dialogue that wasnt a dreadful mis- understanding. This is true also for most prominent cases: Aristotle didnt understand Plato correctly; Hegel . . . of course didnt understand Kant. And Heidegger fundamen- tally didnt understand anyone at all. So, no dialogue. (p. 50) For iek, true philosophers generally do not enter into debates about the issues of the day; they do not take sides or give opinions or provide answers. The rst gesture of the philosopher is usually to point out that the alternatives being put forward are almost always false alternatives or what Deleuze & Guattari (1994) termed a disjunctive synthesis. As iek (2005, p. 51) pointed out, we must change the concepts of the debate, that is, we must re-problematize it, which on the whole is not a popular move with fellow academics, managers, and administrators who wish to solve the current problem rather than create a new one. In his book The Differend, Jean Franois Lyotard made a similar distinction between what he called the intellectual and the philosopher. Whereas the intellec- tual smoothes over difference and generally supports the status quo for the sake of political hegemony (Lyotard, 1983, p. 142), the job of the philosopher is to problematize disputes and discussions by pointing out incommensurabilities and by attempting to keep debates open rather than resolve them through the imposition of hegemonic power. Lyotards statement at the very beginning of his book that The time has come to philosophize (p. xiii) should therefore be read as a call to all academics to resist the production- line mentality of the corporate University of Excel- lence and to open up a new space for Thought that refuses to close down debate and discussion for the sake of an articially coherent, unied, and market- able product. Readings, who was a Lyotard scholar, referred to this attitude of encouraging parallel lines of thought as dissensus. He claimed that it should Thinking as a Subversive Activity 35 2012 Blackwell Publishing Ltd Nursing Philosophy (2013), 14, pp. 2837 form the foundation for a new way of dwelling in the ruins of the corporate University and suggested the need to build a community of Thought, that is, a community committed to dissensus. This is not a com- munity of dissent; not a community of opposition; not a community that likes to say no. Rather, it is a community that, to borrow Deleuze and Guattaris term, says . . . and . . . and . . . and . . .; one that encourages a plurality of conicting opinion with no pressure to achieve a consensus in the name of truth, beauty, or a marketable product (Deleuze & Guattari, 1987, p. 25). A community of dissensus is concerned not with an end product but with reinstating Thought as a process and as a problematic which, as Readings said, does not function as an answer but as a question (Readings, 1996, p. 160). Readingss invitation to dwell among the ruins in communities of Thought can therefore be interpreted as a return to philosophy in its traditional Kantian sense of the lower faculty of the University. This lower faculty would stand apart from the manufac- ture and sale of knowledge, information, and quali- cations that has become the main business of the University and which is now more or less self- perpetuating and immune to internal critique. For Kant, the faculty of philosophy was lower because it renounced political power and authority in return for academic freedom. Transposed to the 21st century, this would rst and foremost entail replacing nancial accountancy with academic accountability. Dwelling in the ruins The time has come to philosophize, that is to say, to challenge and call into question the basic assumptions on which the corporate University rests. This can only be achieved by members of the University itself, and they have to do it while at the same time sustaining the very institution that they are calling to account. Philosophy in the 21st century is no longer something we can do instead of, say, sociology, mathematics, or even nursing. Philosophy in the corporate University must be done alongside our academic specialism, from within our home department or faculty. To do philosophy in this sense is to critique the ethos of the corporate University as it applies to our particular academic discipline, to call into question the unspo- ken assumptions on which that ethos rests, and to challenge and subvert the corporate mission as and when it comes into conict with the professional ethics and values of nursing. To paraphrase the manager cited earlier, our duty as philosophers is to bring problems, not solutions. For nurse academics, this critique might (or perhaps should) include a deep and fundamental questioning of the relationship between research, theory, and practice; of the meaning of education in relation to practice; of why, for whom, and by whom nursing research should be undertaken; and perhaps even of whether the Univer- sity is the best and most appropriate home for nursing education and research. The University is in ruins and there are a number of ways that we, as academics and students, can respond. We can pine nostalgically for the return of the Enlightenment University; we can actively rebel against the corporate machine that has taken its place; or we can sink into an attitude of passive despair. Readings insisted that none of these options were acceptable and argued instead that we should dwell in the ruins without alibis, that is to say, as authentically and productively as we are able, given that we all need at least supercially to satisfy the demands of a corporate mission that we neither agreed nor signed up to. This is arguably more press- ing for nurse academics than for geographers, math- ematicians, and historians. Firstly, as we have seen, there are tangible points of conict and contradiction between the corporate demands of the University and the professional demands of nursing practice. And secondly, the requirement by the nursing profession for competent graduates and effective research is in some cases quite literally a matter of life and death. To paraphrase Heidegger, philosophy must be our way of dwelling in the ruined University. References Badiou A. (2005) Thinking the event. In: Philosophy in the Present (ed. P. Engelman), pp. 148. Polity Press, Cam- bridge, 2009. Badiou A. (2009) Second Manifesto for Philosophy. Polity Press, Cambridge. Gary Rolfe 36 2012 Blackwell Publishing Ltd Nursing Philosophy (2013), 14, pp. 2837 Deleuze G. & Guattari F. (1987) AThousand Plateaus. Uni- versity of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis. Deleuze G. & Guattari F. (1994) What Is Philosophy? Columbia University Press, New York. Habermas J. (1968) Knowledge and Human Interest. Polity Press, Cambridge, 1987. von Humboldt W. (1810) On the spirit and organisational framework of intellectual institutions in Berlin. Minerva, 1970, 8, 242267. Translated by E. Shils. Kant I. (1787) Critique of Pure Reason. Hackett, Indianapo- lis, 1996. Kant I. (1798) The Conict of the Faculties. University of Nebraska Press, Lincoln, 1992. Lyotard J.F. (1979) The Postmodern Condition. Manchester University Press, Manchester, 1984. Lyotard J.F. (1983) The Differend. University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, 1988. Newman J.H. (1858) The Idea of a University. University of Notre Dame Press, Notre Dame, IN, 1892. Nursing and Midwifery Council (NMC) (2008) Standards of Conduct, Performance andEthics for Nurses andMidwives. NMC, London. Available at: http://www.nmc-uk.org/ Nurses-and-midwives/The-code/ [accessed 21 May 2012]. Oakeshott M. (1950) The idea of a university. In: The Voice of Liberal Learning (ed. T. Fuller), pp. 105117. Liberty Fund, Indianapolis, 2001. Readings B. (1996) The University in Ruins. Harvard Uni- versity Press, Cambridge. Swansea University (2009) Strategic Plan 200914. Available at: http://www.swansea.ac.uk/media/media,40519,en.pdf [accessed 23 August 2011]. iek S. (2005) Philosophy in not a dialogue. In: Philosophy in the Present (ed. P. Engelman), pp. 4972. Polity Press, Cambridge, 2009. Thinking as a Subversive Activity 37 2012 Blackwell Publishing Ltd Nursing Philosophy (2013), 14, pp. 2837
Download (Ebook) Towards a Multiversity?: Universities between Global Trends and National Traditions by Georg Krücken (editor); Anna Kosmützky (editor); Marc Torka (editor) ISBN 9783839404683, 3839404681 ebook All Chapters PDF
Download (Ebook) Towards a Multiversity?: Universities between Global Trends and National Traditions by Georg Krücken (editor); Anna Kosmützky (editor); Marc Torka (editor) ISBN 9783839404683, 3839404681 ebook All Chapters PDF