Forensic Media by Greg Siegel
Forensic Media by Greg Siegel
GREG SIEGEL
R E C O N S T R U C T I N G A C C I D E N T S I N A C C E L E R AT E D M O D E R N I T Y
Sign, Storage, Transmission
A series edited by Jonathan Sterne and Lisa Gitelman
Greg Siegel
FORENSIC MEDIA
Reconstructing Accidents in Accelerated Modernity
acknowledgments ix
two. Tracings 65
notes 215
index 251
acknowledgments
The first glimmer of this book came when, during a grad seminar at the Uni-
versity of North Carolina, Chapel Hill, I heard a presentation about the cockpit
voice recorder by Mark Robinson, a gifted audio artist. While the particulars of
his creation now escape me, I remember being fascinated by the way he deftly
integrated actual black- box recordings into an intricate sonic assemblage. The
same seminar introduced me to Paul Virilio’s work on the accident. These were
the seeds.
At the University of North Carolina, I benefited from the wisdom and sup-
port of some outstanding mentors and friends. Larry Grossberg, who guided me
intellectually and professionally during those green years, taught me most of
what I know about cultural studies and the philosophy of communication. He
also nurtured my ability to draw clear conceptual distinctions and to engage in
rigorous critical analysis. What instances of clarity and rigor are to be found in
these pages owe much to his influence. Tyler Curtain, Ken Hillis, Kevin Parker,
Della Pollock, and Barbara Herrnstein Smith (at Duke University) each helped
me to develop and refine the ideas herein, and I am grateful to them. As for
my unc comrades, Gwen Blue, Steve Collins, Andrew Douglas, Rivka Eisner,
Nathan Epley, Mark Hayward, Mark Olson, Phaedra Pezzullo, Bob Rehak, Jona-
than Riehl, and Matt Spangler o≠ered encouragement during the formative
years. Special thanks and praises to Josh Malitsky, Jules Odendahl- James, and
Ted Striphas—three friends whose sage counsel, keen insights, and close fel-
lowship made Forensic Media thinkable.
To say that my colleagues in the film and media studies department at the
University of California, Santa Barbara, have been exceptionally generous and
supportive is to barely scratch the surface. In ways subtle and profound, Edward
Branigan, Peter Bloom, Michael Curtin, Anna Everett, Dick Hebdige, Jennifer
Holt, Ross Melnick, Lisa Parks, Constance Penley, Bhaskar Sarkar, Cristina
Venegas, Janet Walker, and Chuck Wolfe—world- class scholars and wonderful
people all—inspired me, and emboldened me, to see this book through. Extra
gratitude to Jenny for doing her damnedest to keep me on firm footing (amid
the ups) and in good humor (amid the downs). Thanks also to Kathy Murray,
department manager extraordinaire, for her always amiable replies to my many
pesky questions.
Other luminaries at ucsb provided intellectual stimulation, interdisciplin-
ary opportunities, and professional guidance during the writing of this book. I
am indebted to Bishnu Ghosh, Lisa Hajjar, Wolf Kittler, Patrick McCray, David
Novak, Rita Raley, and Russell Samolsky for lending a hand or pointing a way.
I am indebted, as well, to Meredith Bak and Abby Hinsman for their astute,
resourceful, and dedicated research assistance. I thank ucsb’s College of Let-
ters and Science, the Hellman Family, and ucsb’s Interdisciplinary Humanities
Center for the faculty fellowships I received while researching and writing this
book.
For their correspondence or other assistance, I am grateful to Karen Beck-
man, John Brockmann, René Bruckner, James Cahill, Ken Carper, Scott Curtis,
Oliver Gaycken, Lisa Gitelman, Dennis Grossi, James Hay, Sarah Lochlann Jain,
Akira Lippit, Colin Milburn, David Morton, Sina Najafi, Paul Niquette, Jeremy
Packer, Jussi Parikka, John Durham Peters, Henry Petroski, Raymond Pu≠er,
Eric Schatzberg, Jonathan Sterne, Marion Sturkey, Eyal Weizman, Gerald
Wilson, Patrick Wright, and Peter van Wyck. I am incredibly lucky that Karen
and Jonathan, in particular, took an early and sustained interest in this project.
To have two such brilliant and accomplished scholars in my corner—well, it is
hard to express in a few words how much their advice, generosity, and endorse-
ment have meant to me. Each deserves more thanks than I have space here.
If I tried the patience of Courtney Berger, my editor at Duke University
Press, she was gracious enough not to show it. Her thoughtful comments and
steady navigation made this a better book. Thanks also to Erin Hanas at Duke
University Press for her superb editorial assistance, to Danielle Szulczewski for
shepherding the book through the production process, and to Ken Wissoker
for his support.
I am grateful to Ken Goldberg for permission to use his Dislocation of Inti‑
macy image, to Jennifer McDaid at Norfolk Southern Corporation for help with
the train-wreck photos in chapter 1, and to Erin Rushing at the Smithsonian
for help with the Phonogram mermaid illustration. I am especially thankful to
the photographer Je≠rey Milstein for generously allowing me to use his amaz-
ing flight- recorder image for this book’s cover—an image that perfectly evokes
the medium’s danger aura and damaged beauty alike. More of Je≠’s remarkable
work can be viewed at www .je≠reymilstein .com.
x acknowledgments
Finally, this book would not have been possible without the moral support
of friends and family. Encouragement from Jackie Apodaca, Steve Baltin, Betsy
Berman, Julie Bowden, Rick Butler, Andrew Dickler, Debbie Kahler Doles, Jeff
Fishbein, Sheila Flaherty, David Greenberg, Rick Habor, Pete Howard, Ned
Jennison, Gary Komar, Jon Leaver, Craig Leva, David Marcus, James O’Brien,
Tyke O’Brien, Dale Sherman, and my sister Ali Leigh enabled me to keep
keepin’ on. My deepest gratitude is reserved for my parents, Nancy and Barry.
I am beyond fortunate that they have always believed in me and have always
been there for me. With love, I dedicate this book to them.
Acknowledgments xi
introduction
The will to mastery becomes all the more urgent the more technology threatens to slip from
human control. —martinheidegger, “The Question Concerning Technology”
In the disaster milieu, technological civilization is on trial as it attempts to heal the systemic
breach and restore itself through a figural elimination of all risk. Various cultural interpreta-
tions, analyses, and judgments attempt reconstruction of a safe world without slippage, broadly
defined. —annlar abee, Decade of Disaster
fact. On learning of the mishap, Captain Edward A. Murphy Jr., one of the test
technicians, quipped in frustration, “Whatever can go wrong, will go wrong.”
Thus was born Murphy’s Law.
While not as widely known as the adage itself, the Murphy’s Law origin
story has, over the decades, become something of a minor legend.3 As with
all legends, the story circulates in many “true” versions. Was Stapp the one
who rode the rocket sled, or was the test subject actually a chimpanzee? How
many sensors were involved—four? Six? Sixteen? Were they a∞xed to Stapp’s
harness or to his body? Were they mounted incorrectly, or were they defective
from the outset? Was Murphy at fault, or was another technician to blame?
Did Murphy coin the expression on the spot, or did Stapp do so days later at a
press conference? And how, exactly, was the expression worded? Each of the
following phrasings has been claimed as accurate: “If there’s any way they [the
team of technicians] can do it wrong, they will”; “If anything can go wrong, it
will”; “If anything can go wrong, he [Murphy] will do it”; “If it can happen, it
2 introduction
will”;4 “If that guy [Murphy’s assistant] has any way of making a mistake, he
will”; “If there’s more than one way to do a job, and one of those ways will result
in disaster, then somebody will do it that way”; “Whatever can go wrong, will
go wrong.”
Which, if any, version of the origin story is historically true and which, if
any, variant of the adage is historically accurate are less important for our pur-
poses here than the cultural perceptions they collectively articulate. Murphy’s
Law makes a popular truism out of a pessimistic fatalism, extracts a nugget
of folk wisdom from a philosophy of despair. It presumes the failure of every
endeavor and, in a sense, predicts the worst of all possible worlds (and does
so with a hint of perverse delight). It insists that, in the future, mistakes, mis-
fortunes, and other inauspicious outcomes are not only probable but, indeed,
unavoidable. It says that the proverbial best- laid plans always go astray.
Perhaps more intriguing, though, is the singular way in which Murphy’s Law
evinces a certain attitude toward modern technology. Interpreted in the light
of its origin story, with its faulty sensors and frustrated scientists, the enduring
maxim expresses not so much a sweeping cosmological pessimism as a narrow
technological one. “Whatever can go wrong, will go wrong” e≠ectively trans-
lates as “However technology can fail, it will fail.” To be sure, the mythology
surrounding Murphy’s Law reads as a contemporary parable of technologi-
cal excess and accident, a cautionary tale about the irreducible complexity of
human- machine relations and the unruly contingencies that vex—and seem
to hex—them.
Yet even this reading does not quite reach the story’s deeper meaning,
which is attained only when a grand irony is grasped. The irony is this: Stapp’s
rapid- deceleration research was undertaken with the goal of minimizing the
injurious e≠ects of high- speed accidents. Because the experiments were com-
plicated and fraught with di∞culty and danger, extraordinary steps were taken
to ensure the smoothness of operations and the safety of test subjects. Still, the
accident proved irrepressible. The moral of the Murphy’s Law myth? Its devas-
tating subtext? The accident thwarts even the most technologically advanced
attempts to tame it. Its demons possess the power to disturb even the scene of
their own exorcism.
4 introduction
remus 6000 ready to
launch. Photograph
by and courtesy of
Michael Dessner.
6 introduction
and media in the culture of modernity, where “modernity” can be provision-
ally understood, following Matei Calinescu, to denote “a stage in the history
of Western civilization—a product of scientific and technological progress, of
the industrial revolution, of the sweeping economic and social changes brought
about by capitalism.”16 More to the point, this book is about how, since the
nineteenth century, media technologies have informed and facilitated an on-
going project to deal with the problem of technological accidents, particularly
high- speed crashes and catastrophes. Forensic- scientific in nature and method,
this ongoing project, like the problem it enunciates, has multiple intersecting
dimensions: cultural and institutional, practical and epistemological, material
and ideological. My overarching contention in these pages is that accidents,
forensics, and media are mutually implicated in the origins and evolution of a
dominant tendency in modern technological thought, discourse, and practice.
This tendency treats forensic knowledge of accident causation as the key to
the accident’s solution, the rational answer to its constitutive riddle. It also
treats such knowledge as a source of future technical improvement and, by
further (and somewhat fantastic) extension, of future sociotechnological ad-
vancement, of progress on a civilizational scale. Forensic Media examines this
peculiar complex of scientific attitude and cultural mythos by considering
the ways and contexts in which graphic, photographic, electronic, and digital
media have been adapted and deployed to informationalize, anatomize, and
narrativize accidents of accelerated mobility. Throughout, I show how such
devices have been pressed into service to forensically work on, work out, and
work through such disasters: to scientifically detect and inspect them, to epis-
temically manage and discursively control them. In o≠ering a new account of
the historical links and cultural relays between accidents and forensics, I ulti-
mately aim to tell a new story about the corresponding connections between
media, technology, and modernity.
Forensic Media’s case studies and analyses are organized around a set of
critical questions: how have devices of recording, representation, and repro-
duction been employed to scientifically analyze and explain high- speed mis-
haps? What was the historical impetus for so employing them? How do the
imagination and the practice of reconstructing accidents through aural, visual,
and audiovisual media enact a distinctly forensic rationality and epistemol-
ogy? How do such cultural imaginings and institutional practices embody a
larger forensic project and ideology? How do certain forensic media—namely,
Charles Babbage’s “self- registering apparatus” (chapter 2), flight- data recorders
and cockpit voice recorders (chapter 3), crash- test cinematography (chapter 4),
and accident- reconstruction technologies (epilogue)—rearticulate other, older
8 introduction
Philosophical system builders and Christian providentialists are not the only
ones to categorically refuse the accidental, or so it has been authoritatively
claimed. In his treatise The Child’s Conception of Physical Causality (1927), the
developmental psychologist Jean Piaget argued that young children, like Aris-
totle (the comparison is Piaget’s), feel “a very definite repugnance” for the idea
of chance:
Five years earlier, the philosopher and armchair anthropologist Lucien Lévy-
Bruhl described the “primitive mentality” in much the same way:
We say that the granary collapsed because its supports were eaten away
by termites. That is the cause that explains the collapse of the granary.
We also say that people were sitting under it at the time because it was in
the heat of the day and they thought that it would be a comfortable place
to talk and work. This is the cause of people being under the granary at
the time it collapsed. To our minds the only relationship between these
two independently caused facts is their coincidence in time and space.
We have no explanation of why the two chains of causation intersected
at a certain time and in a certain place, for there is no interdependence
between them.
Zande philosophy can supply the missing link. The Zande knows that
the supports were undermined by termites and that people were sitting
beneath the granary in order to escape the heat and glare of the sun. But
he knows besides why these two events occurred at a precisely similar
moment in time and space. It was due to the action of witchcraft. If there
had been no witchcraft people would have been sitting under the granary
and it would not have fallen on them, or it would have collapsed but the
people would not have been sheltering under it at the time. Witchcraft
explains the coincidence of these two happenings.25
In these scholarly accounts from the early twentieth century, child and
“primitive” alike inhabit a maximally enchanted world—a world naturally re-
plete with moral significance and supernaturally devoid of mere coincidence.
Just as the child’s proscription of chance is simultaneously an index of his im-
maturity and a function of his pre- rationality, so the primitive’s nonconcep-
tion of the accidental is a token of both his unscientificity and his uncivil-
ity—indeed, is regarded as the very mark and measure of his distance from a
normative Western modernity. For Lévy- Bruhl and Evans- Pritchard, the ability
to apprehend the ordinary workings of contingency, to recognize in certain oc-
currences an irreducible accidentality—to acknowledge, in short, the fact that
some things “just happen”—is precisely an achievement of reason and scien-
tific enlightenment. Belief in the element of chance, acceptance of mere co-
incidence, serves as a standard of intellectual sophistication and an expression
of cultural superiority. Primitive peoples, what with their “superstitious” cos-
10 introduction
mologies, imagine that magical or animistic forces are necessarily implicated
in the realization of nearly every unfortunate event. Modern populations (“us
Europeans”), by contrast, having renounced the myth of supernatural influ-
ence, are supposed to understand that much of what happens in the world does
so without intention or motivation and, therefore, contains no intrinsic mean-
ing or purpose. Epistemological modernity makes accidents possible as such.
Judith Green has located the accidental’s modern provenance in the fissure
between two articles of rationalist faith, in the slippage between two prevailing
scientisms.26 The first of these is the belief in the laws of physical causation vis-
à-vis the production of events; the second, the belief in the laws of statistical
probability vis- à-vis the distribution of those events. On the one hand, modern
reason avows that every misfortune, like every other occurrence (willed or
not, foreseen or not), is the e≠ect of a concrete, determinate cause or chain
of causes. On the other hand, it knows that any particular misfortune, any
specific instance of “bad luck,” is (or was, before it came to pass) always only a
mathematical possibility, not a preordained certainty, not “destiny.” After the
Enlightenment, the philosophical and discursive adhesive that holds these two
propositions together, that joins causal determinism to statistical probabilism,
physical necessity to phenomenal contingency, takes the name “accident.”
“An accident appears in the gaps left by a rationalist cosmology, at the limit of
deterministic laws, but where superstition no longer has a legitimate part to
play,” writes Green in Risk and Misfortune. “These gaps in rationalist explana-
tions emerge between what is known for sure (that is, that which is subject
to deterministic laws, such as those describing the motions of planets around
the sun, or gravity on the earth) and that which is known statistically (that is,
that which is subject to the laws of probability, such as the chance of reaching
a certain age or of dying of a certain disease).”27 In a similar vein, Octavio Paz
contends that “the Accident has become a paradox of necessity: it possesses the
fatality of necessity and at the same time the indetermination of freedom.”28
At once excessive to the system and, paradoxically, like the Derridian “sup-
plement,” an excess the system requires for self- coherence and self- completion,
the “residual category” of the accidental is crucial to modern thought and dis-
course because it functions to stabilize the fault line between deterministic and
probabilistic logics, without resorting to interpretations rooted in either provi-
dential or “primitive” worldviews.29 “To classify,” declares Zygmunt Bauman in
Modernity and Ambivalence, “is to give the world a structure: to manipulate its
probabilities; to make some events more likely than some others; to behave as
if events were not random, or to limit or eliminate randomness of events.”30
12 introduction
An immense volume of force had detached itself from the unknown universe
of energy, while still vaster reservoirs, supposed to be infinite, steadily revealed
themselves.”32
Adams’s literary description of modern technology’s “accidental” inflictions
and innervations, besides resonating with certain of the urban sociological
writings of Georg Simmel, Siegfried Kracauer, and Walter Benjamin, paral-
leled the sensational depictions of metropolitan modernity in the fin- de- siècle
press. As Ben Singer observes, “The sense of a radically altered public space,
one defined by chance, peril, and shocking impressions rather than by any
traditional conception of continuity and self- controlled destiny,” pervaded the
illustrated newspapers—and, with them, the popular imagination—of the day.
“Unnatural death . . . had been a source of fear in premodern times as well . . . ,
but the violence, suddenness, [and] randomness . . . of accidental death in the
metropolis appear to have intensified and focalized this fear.”33
The novel causes and fearsome circumstances of accidental injury and death
in the nineteenth century prompted a broad range of social, cultural, technical,
and institutional responses. In general, these responses were predicated on dis-
tinctly modern logics and discourses of risk and safety. Hence the ascendance
of a certain dual practico- ideological imperative: minimize/reduce the former,
maximize/produce the latter.
Both Ulrich Beck and Anthony Giddens have argued that modernity invests
the concept of risk with a unique meaning and with a special epistemological
function. In Beck’s now- classic formulation, “risk” names “a systematic way of
dealing with hazards and insecurities induced and introduced by moderniza-
tion itself. Risks, as opposed to older dangers, are consequences which relate
to the threatening force of modernization and to its globalization of doubt.”34
In contrast to premodern societies, which ascribed calamities and other mis-
fortunes to the gods or demons, to the fates or Fortuna, modern industrialized
societies, according to Beck and Giddens, take pains to turn disasters and other
unfortunate contingencies into rationally calculable risks. “A world structured
mainly by humanly created risks has little place for divine influences, or indeed
for the magical propitiation of cosmic forces or spirits,” writes Giddens in The
Consequences of Modernity, sounding very much like Lévy- Bruhl and Evans-
Pritchard (sans their colonialist ethnocentrism).35 “It is central to modernity
that risks can in principle be assessed in terms of generalisable knowledge
about potential dangers—an outlook in which notions of fortuna mostly survive
as marginal forms of superstition.”36
François Ewald, for his part, traces the concept back to the realm of late
medieval maritime insurance, wherein “risk designated the possibility of an
14 introduction
and twentieth centuries witnessed the birth and di≠usion of a new precaution-
ary ethos and consciousness, embodied in all manner of safety movements and
campaigns, safety laws and regulations, safety systems and procedures, safety
tools and equipment, safety organizations and cultures, safety experts and pro-
fessionals. In so-called risk societies, where technological accidents “just hap-
pen” and, moreover, are forever “waiting to happen,” where (per Singer) they
materialize violently, suddenly, and randomly, safety is simultaneously a worthy
objective and an everyday obsession, a perfectly reasonable aim and a patently
anxious fixation.
“Safety is often considered to be a bu≠er between technology run rampant
and the sanctity of human life,” notes Jeremy Packer, “a zone that protects hu-
manity from the modernization machine, the greed of corporations, speed,
the crash, the insensitivity of the bureaucratic monster, and breakdowns in
the moral order.”44 Since the onset of industrialization, modern subjects and
populations have been told time and again that the problem of the accident
(the crash, the breakdown, the monster in the machine) has its solution in
the provision of safety, in the expansion of that bu≠er, that zone, that protec-
tive space, literal or metaphorical, separating sacred life from risky technology,
cushioning the one against the other.
Over the past two centuries, many and various technical “safety devices”
have been employed in many and various contexts. Rem Koolhaas, in “ ‘Life
in the Metropolis’ or ‘The Culture of Congestion,’ ” recounts a legendary story
about one exemplary such device:
In 1853, at Manhattan’s first World’s Fair, the invention that would, more
than any other, become the “sign” of the Metropolitan Condition, was
introduced to the public in a singularly theatrical format.
Elisha Otis, the inventor of the elevator, mounts a platform. The plat-
form ascends. When it has reached its highest level, an assistant presents
Otis with a dagger on a velvet cushion. The inventor takes the knife and
attacks what appears the crucial component of his invention: the cable
that has hoisted the platform upward and that now prevents its fall. Otis
cuts the cable; nothing happens to platform or inventor.
Invisible safety- catches prevent the platform from rejoining the sur-
face of the earth. They represent the essence of Otis’s invention: the abil-
ity to prevent the elevator from crashing.
Like the elevator, each technical invention is pregnant with a double
image: the spectre of its possible failure. The way to avert that phantom
disaster is as important as the original invention itself.45
Unknown Causes
To problematize the accident is, first of all, to pose the question of the acci-
dent’s cause. In technologically modern societies, questions of accident causa-
tion are investigated forensically. They are investigated, that is to say, through
the scientific detection and inspection of material traces, the formal decoding
of indexical signs, the rigorous analysis of physical evidence. Queries are put to
the remains of the catastrophe (including its mediatized remains: its recorded
survivals, its “living” reproductions) as though they were a criminal suspect
under police interrogation or, still more appositely, a corpse under the disci-
plinary gaze of an autopsist or pathological anatomist. What really happened?
What went wrong? What were the precipitating factors? What were the oc-
casioning circumstances? What was the exact sequence of events, the relevant
chain of causes? What, in short, is the story of the accident?
The need or desire to search out and understand the causal origins of ac-
cidents and unfortunate events—and to quell the panic or terror such occur-
rences are liable to engender—is, according to both Thomas Hobbes and David
Hume, not only a profoundly human but also a primordially religious impulse.
“It is peculiar to the nature of man to be inquisitive into the causes of the
events they see, some more, some less, but all men so much as to be curious
in the search of the causes of their own good and evil fortune,” Hobbes pro-
claims.46 “The perpetual fear, always accompanying mankind in the ignorance
of causes (as it were in the dark), must needs have for object something. And
therefore, when there is nothing to be seen, there is nothing to accuse, either
of their good or evil fortune, but some power or agent invisible; in which sense,
perhaps, it was that some of the old poets said that the gods were at first created
by human fear.”47
A hundred- odd years after Hobbes’s Leviathan, Hume, in his Natural His‑
tory of Religion, argued along the same lines, with characteristic eloquence:
“We are placed in this world, as in a great theatre, where the true springs
and causes of every event are entirely concealed from us; nor have we either
16 introduction
su∞cient wisdom to foresee, or power to prevent those ills, with which we are
continually threatened. We hang in perpetual suspence [sic] between life and
death, health and sickness, plenty and want; which are distributed amongst
the human species by secret and unknown causes, whose operation is oft un-
expected, and always unaccountable. These unknown causes, then, become the
constant object of our hope and fear.”48 And then, a few paragraphs on: “Every
disastrous accident alarms us, and sets us on enquires concerning the prin-
ciples whence it arose: Apprehensions spring up with regard to futurity: And
the mind, sunk into di∞dence, terror, and melancholy, has recourse to every
method of appeasing those secret intelligent powers, on whom our fortune is
supposed entirely to depend.”49
When bad things happen unexpectedly or unaccountably, these modern phi-
losophers insist, we are anxious to know why. Disaster strikes, and we instinc-
tively strive to dissipate the enveloping epistemic darkness. Nothing, it seems,
is so intolerable, so upsetting or threatening, as an unknown cause. Gripped
by fear, plagued by ignorance, impelled by curiosity, we go in quest of answers
and reassurance. Defensively, we are inclined to investigate the accident’s mys-
terious genesis, its obscure “springs and causes”; desperately, we try to propiti-
ate the invisible superintending intelligence that allegedly dispenses fortune
and misfortune, allocates good and evil, weal and woe. “Cause,” says Roland
Barthes, is “an ironically ambiguous word, referring as it does to a faith and a
determinism, as if they were the same thing.”50 Hobbes and Hume alike postu-
late that the masses of humankind, ever insecure about their uncertain future,
have, over the millennia, tended to put their faith in God or the gods, hoping
and praying, trusting and believing that every worldly occurrence, favorable or
not, has a purposeful cause, and every cause a higher reason.
In the religious imagination, then, the mundane cause of any given acci-
dent or unfortunate event is identical to the transmundane reason for it. The
will of God or of the gods is construed as mover, motion, and motive, all at
once. “They that believe God dos [sic] not foresee Accidents, because Nothing
can be known that is not, and Accidents have no being, untill [sic] they are in
Act, are very much mistaken,” declares the seventeenth- century man of letters
Samuel Butler. “For Accident is but a Terme [sic] invented to relieve Ignorance
of Causes, as Physitians [sic] use to call the strange operations of Plants, and
Mineralls [sic] Occult Qualities, not that they are without their Causes, but
that their Causes are unknown. And indeed there is not any thing in Nature,
or event, that ha’s [sic] not a Pedegree [sic] of Causes, which though obscure to
us, cannot be so to God, who is the first Cause of all things.”51
Modern reason and technology conspire to complicate this theistic picture.
18 introduction
new scientifico- legal discipline (criminalistics) in reciprocal association with a
new literary fictional genre and protagonist (the detective story, the detective-
hero); it also sowed the seeds of that cognate discipline that would, in the
twentieth century, come to be called “forensic engineering.”
Railroad Accidents: Their Causes and the Means of Preventing Them, written by
the French civil engineer Emile With and translated into English in 1856, was
probably the first nontechnical treatise to take an incipiently forensic approach
to the problem of mechanized- transportation accidents. “For some months,
railroad accidents have become so common, that it seems as though science
was altogether powerless in preventing them,” With asserts. “In truth, they
are always occasioned by the imprudence of passengers, the want of foresight
in those employed on the road, or by a concurrence of fatal, but very natural
circumstances.”53 Pro≠ering rationalist explanations of phenomena ranging
from “Explosion of Locomotive Boilers” to “Carelessness of Those in Charge
of Engines,” from “Defects in the Rolling Stock” to “Want of Communication
Between the Conductor and Engine Driver,” Railroad Accidents concludes that
every train wreck can be attributed either to operator error or to a “fatal” (but
not fated) conjunction of “very natural” (as against supernatural) forces and
conditions. Furthermore, because railroad accidents happen for these, and only
these, sublunary reasons, because their causes are traceable often to human
behavior and always to brute physics, science is by no means “powerless” to
intervene and improve the situation. On the contrary, With assures his readers,
by discovering and elucidating the root causes of catastrophes, science demon-
strates that “it is never impossible to prevent” the occurrence of similar mis-
fortunes in the future.54 “In all countries, [railroads] are subjects of study with
serious minds, and they are every day advancing more nearly to perfection.”55
In his preface, With’s translator, G. Forrester Barstow, also a civil engineer,
protests (as if echoing Samuel Butler in a secular register) that railroad acci-
dents do not truly deserve their common appellation:
Accidents are defined by Webster to be, “events which proceed from un-
known causes, or unusual e≠ects of known causes.” Any result, which
is the natural and regular e≠ect of a known cause, be that cause what it
may, cannot be called an accident. In this light, we are persuaded that the
word is greatly misapplied to the various tragic occurrences which take
place upon our railroads.
Words are sometimes things; for persons, who would look upon an ac‑
cident, as a thing to be lamented or borne with resignation, but with the
production or prevention of which they had little or nothing to do, might
20 introduction
sionate story of causal concatenation (greeted as reassuringly natural). To this
end, devices and protocols of forensic mediation are tasked with restoring to
the disaster—to its fractured temporality, to its uncertain ontology—a strict
chronology, a precise ordering of time, along with a stable narrativity, a plot- like
arrangement of events. Endowed ex post facto with measurable duration and
intelligible succession, with an essential unity and integrity, the catastrophe
thereby acquires a mundane cause and, at the same time, a meaningful reason.
And, as Friedrich Nietzsche observes, “reasons bring relief.”57 In our age of
forensic enlightenment, this is how the technological accident is both engaged
and assuaged: how its happening is authoritatively explained, how its strange-
ness is made comfortably familiar, how its secret becomes o∞cially known.
This is the way that its “shocking impressions” are ideally attenuated, its ner-
vous “apprehensions” culturally negotiated, its perpetual threat ideologically
contained.
There is no denying that the forensic sciences and forensic engineering
have produced, and continue to produce, remarkable results in the spheres of
medicine, law enforcement, criminal justice, technology, and architecture and
design, to name a conspicuous few. In these and similar arenas, forensic ideas,
instruments, and procedures undoubtedly “work” (more or less, most of the
time). Forensic science marshals its armamentarium to identify anonymous
corpses, to establish etiologies of death and disease, to facilitate criminal ar-
rests and convictions. Forensic engineering does the same to pinpoint causes
of mechanical and structural failures, to determine responsibility, to assist in
apportioning blame. Thus does that institutionally sanctioned precipitate of
forensic processing—namely, forensic evidence—become socially useful as
well as juridically and politically e≠ectual. Thus do forensic ways of seeing,
knowing, and believing function to mold cultural sensibilities, to make “com-
mon sense.”
Yet, however much convinced by the answers furnished by forensic engi-
neering, we moderns remain only partially reconciled to them—not quite ap-
peased by what we have learned, not quite at peace with what we know, not
quite adjusted to the “truth” of the accident. For after all the inspecting and
analyzing and interpreting and explaining is done, a faint anxiety still hangs;
a hint of disquiet persists. We cannot shake the uneasy suspicion that forensic
logic, despite its scientific validity and its demonstrated utility, fails somehow
to close the epistemological circuit. Its certainties do not totally satisfy. If it
succeeds in providing a map of the accident’s sequence of events, that map,
detailed as it might be, nonetheless discloses only so much, takes us only so
far in our understanding. A moment- by- moment account of “what really hap-
22 introduction
enon most easily grasped by the notion of flow,” time becomes “a troublesome
and anxiety- producing entity that must be thought in relation to management,
regulation, storage, and representation.”61
Forensic media participate in the grand project of arresting, managing, regu-
lating, and representing the troublesome accidentality of time in modernity.
To be sure, they embody, in their own peculiar manner, the impulse to ex-
hibit traumatizing chance, to archive suddenness and shocking contingency,
to impart a semblance of order and meaning to the accident’s irruptions and
inflictions. In their analog incarnations (graphic, mechanical- acoustic, photo-
graphic, analog- electronic), forensic media claim a privileged relation to the
real based on an epistemology of the indexical trace, which trace is regarded
as the authenticating sign of presence, the guarantor of “the condition of the
having- been- there,” as Rosalind Krauss (following Roland Barthes) puts it.62
In their newer, digital- electronic incarnations, forensic media deliver putative
truths through the agency and cultural authority of the computer program,
“hard data” through the lightning e∞ciencies of the algorithm and the micro-
processor. Pertinent as they are, these technical attributes and epistemological
ascriptions do not in themselves serve to sharply di≠erentiate forensic- media
forms and practices, as I conceive them in these pages, from other kinds of
evidentiary- or documentary- media forms and practices. So, then, what dis-
tinguishes them?
I focus on two basic applications of forensic media vis- à-vis accidents of
accelerated mobility, and these applications complement one another both in-
stitutionally and ideologically. On the one hand, forensic media are used in
retrospect to scientifically discover the precise causes and circumstances of
an unplanned high- speed crash (as were the black boxes of Air France Flight
447). On the other hand, they are used in a deliberately staged “accident” to
scientifically dissect the complicated motions and concussions of fast- moving
vehicles and forcefully thrown bodies (as were the overcranked cameras that
recorded John Paul Stapp’s rocket- sled experiments). Modern life is continually
beset by injurious mishaps and ruinous breakdowns, its daily rhythms ineluc-
tably subject to violent interruption from myriad technological collapses and
failures, collisions and malfunctions. Whether in solemn response to the latest
catastrophe or in anxious anticipation of the next one—present- day crash tests
are, in Karen Beckman’s felicitous phrase, “cinematically documented ‘pre-
enactments’ of future technological disasters”—forensic media are routinely
enlisted as superhuman detectives or, alternatively, to borrow Steven Shapin
and Simon Scha≠er’s coinage, as “virtual witnesses.”63 Time and again, they
are called upon to search for telltale clues, to trace hidden causal nexuses, to
24 introduction
what these detectivist observances, these reconstructionist performances, have
to do with speculative prognosis. How is it that acts of retrospection here entail
those of prospection? What, exactly, does the empirical science of forensics
owe to—or, asked more ominously, how is it haunted by—the conjectural arts
of foreseeing, foreknowing, forecasting, foretelling?
The spectral debt in question has a long and suitably weird lineage. As Carlo
Ginzburg notes in his essay “Clues: Roots of an Evidential Paradigm,” prehis-
toric hunters and Mesopotamian diviners alike had to be skillful readers and
interpreters of natural signs, expert decipherers of their material and physical
environments. In order “to discover the traces of events that could not be di-
rectly experienced by the observer,” both the Stone Age hunter and the Bronze
Age soothsayer carried out “minute investigation[s] of even trifling matters.”67
Such traces comprised “excrement, tracks, hairs, feathers, in one case; animals’
innards, drops of oil on the water, heavenly bodies, involuntary movements of
the body, in the other.”68 Their vastly di≠erent historico- anthropological con-
texts notwithstanding, these two types of evidence, of visual, tactile, or olfactory
clue—primitive- venatic and ancient- prophetic—demanded “formally identi-
cal” methods of sensing and decoding: “analyses, comparisons, classifications.”69
26 introduction
its unceasing flow of inventions, had something of the miracle that roused the
fantasy of the masses.”72 Indeed, by the second half of the nineteenth century,
with mechanization working its “miracle” in Western Europe and the United
States, the notion of human progress—now firmly equated with technological
progress—had, according to Bruce Mazlish and Leo Marx, “come to dominate
the worldview of an entire culture.”73
The concept of progress confronted novel and formidable challenges begin-
ning in the early twentieth century. If, as Michael Adas contends, scientific and
technological gauges of human worth and potential ruled European thought
and (geo)political practice during the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries,
the agonies and atrocities of the First World War (the torturous stalemate in
the trenches, the murderous e∞ciency of the new industrialized weaponry)
more than implied that those gauges were in need of recalibration, that the
West’s evaluation of its own moral and material preeminence was dangerously
delusional, maybe even self- defeating.74 For the conflict’s mechanization of
slaughter ultimately evinced not so much humanity’s mastery of nature as its
brutal subjugation to the very tools and techniques that emblematized and
were supposed to enable that mastery. In the eyes of many moderns, the dream
of technological progress had turned into a nightmare:
Giedion, reflecting in the aftermath of the Second World War, agreed: “It may
well be that there are no people left, however remote, who have not lost their
faith in progress. Men have become frightened by progress, changed from a
hope to a menace. Faith in progress lies on the scrap heap, along with many
other devaluated symbols.”76
It has often been alleged that the idea of progress was fatally undermined
two years before the outbreak of the First World War, with the sinking of the
“unsinkable” Royal Mail Steamer Titanic. In truth, the tragedy that befell the Ti‑
28 introduction
could proceed without deviation or delay. Forensics inaugurated a change in
the basic terms of this equation, assigning to the presumedly negative accident
a new and normatively positive use- value. To be exact, it transformed the acci-
dent into an object lesson in faulty engineering, a real- life illustration of unsafe
design. As such, the accident was not just an occasion for scientific inquiry but
an opportunity for practical technical instruction; not just an occurrence that
government and industry learned about but one that engineers and designers
learned from. Forensic discourse thereby recast dystopian catastrophe as uto-
pian possibility. No longer “negative indicators,” accidents became negative
examples, were redeemed as “teachable moments.” Once cursed as threats to
progress, failures and disasters were now hailed as potential levers thereof. As
Theodor Adorno, contradicting the elegists of progress (the Jameses, the Inges,
the Giedions), stated in a 1962 lecture,
More recently, Paul Virilio, following Hannah Arendt, has called the accident
“the hidden face of technical and scientific progress.”82
While Adorno and Virilio each astutely perceive the necessary reciprocity
of progress and catastrophe, neither ponders the historical conditionality of
that reciprocity (or, what is here the same thing, the historical contingency of
that necessity). For them, progress is what it is and always was, and the acci-
dent always was and is implicated—dialectically, as Adorno says—in progress’s
rudimentary “principle.” Such a perspective is essentialist and ahistorical in its
abstraction. For just as there is no immutable Nature of Accident, so there is no
transcendent Law of Progress, dialectical or otherwise. Rather, there is always
only “progress,” always only “accident,” and always only the variable historical
conditions and various discursive constructions of their interrelation. Before
the dawn of forensic enlightenment, progress was said to march linearly and
catastrophe signified backward directionality; since then, however, the two
30 introduction
notes
introduction. accidentsandforensics
1. Until 1949, Edwards Air Force Base was known as Muroc Army Air Field.
2. On Stapp’s rocket- sled experiments at Edwards, see Stapp, “Human Exposures to
Linear Deceleration”; Spark, “The Fastest Man on Earth”; and Stapp, “Human Tolerance
to Deceleration.”
3. My discussion of the legend of Murphy’s Law draws on Spark, “The Fastest Man on
Earth.”
4. This uncommon variant is notable as the only one that does not imply the notion of
error or failure.
5. “Crash of Flight 447.”
6. Downie and Wald, “More Bodies Recovered Near Site of Plane Crash,” www
.nytimes .com/2009/06/08/world/americas/08plane .html.
7. Clark, “Bodies from 2009 Air France Crash Are Found,” http://www .nytimes .com
/2011/05/17/world/europe/04airfrance .html.
8. Clark, “Silence Still from Resting Place of Air France Recorder,” http://query
.nytimes .com/gst/fullpage .html?res=9B02E7D61E3DF933A05755C0A96F9C8B63.
9. Clark, “Bodies from 2009 Air France Crash Are Found.”
10. See Clark, “Bodies from 2009 Air France Crash Are Found”; and Hylton, “The
Deepest End.” remus is an acronym for Remote Environmental Monitoring Unit Sys-
tem.
11. Clark, “Second Black Box Found in Air France Crash,” www .nytimes .com/2011/05
/04/world/europe/04airfrance .html.
12. Clark, “Data Recovered from Air France Flight Recorders,” www .nytimes
.com/2011/05/17/world/europe/17airfrance .html.
13. Ibid.
14. Bureau d’Enquêtes et d’Analyses pour la Sécurité de l’Aviation Civile, Final Report
on the Accident on 1st June 2009 to the Airbus A330‑203, 203.
15. I borrow the term protocols from Lisa Gitelman, who writes that protocols “include
a vast clutter of normative rules and default conditions, which gather and adhere like a
nebulous array around a technological nucleus. Protocols express a huge variety of social,
economic, and material relationships” (Always Already New, 7).
16. Calinescu, Five Faces of Modernity, 41.
17. G. W. F. Hegel, quoted in Marquard, In Defense of the Accidental, 109.
18. Witmore, Culture of Accidents, 43.
19. Ibid., 2.
20. Ibid.
21. Piaget, The Child’s Conception of Physical Causality, 117– 18.
22. Lévy- Bruhl, Primitive Mentality, 43.
23. See Evans- Pritchard, “Lévy- Bruhl’s Theory of Primitive Mentality.”
24. Evans- Pritchard, Witchcraft, Oracles and Magic among the Azande, 72.
25. Ibid., 70.
26. Judith Green, Risk and Misfortune. See also Judith Green, “Accidents.”
27. Green, Risk and Misfortune, 58.
28. Paz, Conjunctions and Disjunctions, 112.
29. On the “supplement,” see Derrida, Of Grammatology. On the “residual category,”
see Judith Green, Risk and Misfortune; and Judith Green, “Accidents.”
30. Bauman, Modernity and Ambivalence, 1.
31. Quoted in Marx, The Machine in the Garden, 170.
32. Henry Adams, The Education of Henry Adams, 495.
33. Singer, Melodrama and Modernity, 70– 71.
34. Beck, Risk Society, 21, emphasis omitted.
35. Giddens, The Consequences of Modernity, 111. See also Giddens, Modernity and Self‑
Identity.
36. Ibid.
37. Ewald, “Two Infinities of Risk,” 226.
38. Ibid.
39. Ibid. See also Ewald, “Insurance and Risk.”
40. Foucault, Politics, Philosophy, Culture, 257. See also Foucault, “Polemics, Politics,
and Problemizations.”
41. Foucault, Power/Knowledge, 131.
42. Cooter and Luckin, “Accidents in History,” 3. See also Hacking, The Emergence of
Probability; Hacking, The Taming of Chance; and Hacking, “How Should We Do the His-
tory of Statistics?”
43. Cooter and Luckin, “Accidents in History,” 4.
44. Packer, “Disciplining Mobility,” 149.
45. Koolhaas, “ ‘Life in the Metropolis’ or ‘The Culture of Congestion,’ ” 324– 25.
46. Hobbes, Leviathan, 63.
47. Ibid., 64.
48. Hume, The Natural History of Religion, 140.
49. Ibid., 143.
50. Barthes, The Grain of the Voice, 115.
51. Butler, Prose Observations, 33.
52. Foucault, Discipline and Punish, 23.
53. With, Railroad Accidents, 11.
54. Ibid.
55. Ibid., 124– 25.
216 notestointroduction
56. Barstow, preface, vi.
57. Nietzsche, On the Genealogy of Morality, 104. Nietzsche’s critique of “the causal
instinct” in Twilight of the Idols is pertinent here: “To derive something unknown from
something familiar relieves, comforts, and satisfies, besides giving a feeling of power.
With the unknown, one is confronted with danger, discomfort, and care; the first instinct
is to abolish these painful states. . . . The causal instinct is thus conditional upon, and
excited by, the feeling of fear. . . . Thus one searches not only for some kind of explanation
to serve as a cause, but for a particularly selected and preferred kind of explanation—that
which has most quickly and most frequently abolished the feeling of the strange, new, and
hitherto unexperienced: the most habitual explanations” (The Portable Nietzsche, 497).
58. Lévi- Strauss, Structural Anthropology, 209.
59. Žižek, The Sublime Object of Ideology, 3.
60. Doane, The Emergence of Cinematic Time, 10.
61. Ibid., 33– 34.
62. Krauss, The Originality of the Avant‑Garde and Other Modernist Myths, 218.
63. Beckman, Crash, 131. On the role of “virtual witnessing” in the history of science,
see Shapin and Scha≠er, Leviathan and the Air‑Pump, 60– 63.
64. Foucault, The Birth of the Clinic, 90, emphasis omitted.
65. Ibid., emphasis omitted.
66. Ibid.
67. Ginzburg, Clues, Myths, and the Historical Method, 103.
68. Ibid.
69. Ibid.
70. The full- length essay was first published in English, with a translation by Anna
Davin, as “Morelli, Freud and Sherlock Holmes: Clues and Scientific Method,” History
Workshop: A Journal of Socialist Historians 9 (spring 1980): 5– 36. A few years later, it was
reprinted under the title “Clues: Morelli, Freud, and Sherlock Holmes,” in The Sign of
Three: Dupin, Holmes, Peirce, ed. Umberto Eco and Thomas A. Sebeok (Bloomington:
Indiana University Press, 1983), 81– 118. In 1989, the essay was retranslated and retitled
for inclusion in Ginzburg’s book Clues, Myths, and the Historical Method.
71. Nisbet, History of the Idea of Progress, 4– 5, emphasis omitted.
72. Giedion, Mechanization Takes Command, 31. Lewis Mumford makes essentially the
same point: “With the rapid improvement of machines, the vague eighteenth century
doctrine [of progress] received new confirmation in the nineteenth century. The laws of
progress became self- evident: were not new machines being invented every year? Were
they not transformed by successive modifications? Did not chimneys draw better, were
not houses warmer, had not railroads been invented?” (Technics and Civilization, 182).
73. Mazlish and Marx, “Introduction,” 1.
74. Adas, Machines as the Measure of Men.
75. Ibid., 379– 80.
76. Giedion, Mechanization Takes Command, 715.
77. Schivelbusch, The Railway Journey, 131.
78. Doane, “Information, Crisis, Catastrophe,” 231.
79. Žižek, The Sublime Object of Ideology, 70.
notestointroduction 217
80. Marx, “The Domination of Nature and the Redefinition of Progress,” 210. Nisbet
writes, “There is . . . good ground for supposing that when the identity of [the twentieth]
century is eventually fixed by historians, not faith but abandonment of faith in the idea
of progress will be one of the major attributes” (History of the Idea of Progress, 317).
81. Adorno, “Progress,” 94.
82. Virilio, Politics of the Very Worst, 92. See also Arendt: “Progress and catastrophe are
the opposite faces of the same coin” (quoted in Virilio, Unknown Quantity, 40).
218 notestointroduction