0% found this document useful (0 votes)
55 views50 pages

Acoustic Specification of Object Properties

Claudia Carello,1,2 Jeffrey B. Wagman,1 and M. T. Turvey1,2 1Center for the Ecological Study of Perception and Action University of Connecticut 2Haskins Laboratories New Haven, CT
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
Download as pdf or txt
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
55 views50 pages

Acoustic Specification of Object Properties

Claudia Carello,1,2 Jeffrey B. Wagman,1 and M. T. Turvey1,2 1Center for the Ecological Study of Perception and Action University of Connecticut 2Haskins Laboratories New Haven, CT
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1/ 50

Ecological acoustics

Acoustic Specification of Object Properties

Claudia Carello,1,2 Jeffrey B. Wagman,1 and M. T. Turvey1,2


1
Center for the Ecological Study of Perception and Action

University of Connecticut
2
Haskins Laboratories

New Haven, CT

Abstract

A general statement of the ecological approach to perception is that a particular animal-

environment relation or event lawfully structures energy distributions that specify the event that

generated them. A given event can, of course, structure varied energy media simultaneously, but

how richly? Precise information about geometric propertiesthe sizes and shapes of

objectshas long been assumed to be the province of visual perception. But the foregoing

ecological law statement suggests that this limitation is more tradition than necessity. Since an

objects physical parameters and its spatial dimensions determine the acoustic structure it

generates when mechanically disturbed, such structure is potentially informative about object

properties. We describe research showing that the perception of object properties by sound alone

is reliable, surprisingly accurate, and constrained by dynamical law.


Ecological acoustics

Acoustic Specification of Object Properties

A bottle sits unseen on the kitchen counter. Your elbow clips it inadvertently and sends it

hurtling towards the floor. As you cringe, waiting for the crash, what you hear is not a shattering

mess but a harmless bounce. The impact of glass on linoleum has set the materials into vibration,

generating compression waves in the air. Somehow, from this sound structure, you know that the

bottle did not break. Moreover, the people listening in the dining room heard something bounce

as well. Lets focus on those listeners whose only contact with the event is from sound. What

else do they know about what happened? Can they hear, for example, that the fallen object was

made of glass, that it was a bottle, whether it was large or small, full or empty?

The preceding questions concern what listeners perceive about events happening around

them. On the basis of its inattention to such questions, the science of perception can be

considered skeptical that audition makes us aware of our surroundings with anything

approaching the level of precision that vision allows (Jenkins, 1985). Hearings specialties are

thought to lie in perceiving speech and music. Beyond orienting the listener to the direction of a

crash, hearing isnt considered to be of much use in obtaining information about geometric

properties, such as letting us know the sizes and shapes of objects. At least this has been the bias

of orthodox approaches to perception. Shape and space perception are the traditional province of

vision; pitch and loudness perception are the traditional domain of audition. Whereas vision is

about awareness of environmental properties, audition seems to be largely about the awareness

of sound as such.

Orthodoxy, of course, is likely to inspire heterodoxy. For perception, a contrary treatment

can be found in the ecological approach of James Gibson. A major innovation is its focus on

perceiving object properties rather than sound propertieshearing a small, hollow, glass object
Ecological acoustics

falling onto a hard surface rather than a loud, low-pitched, brief sound. In what follows, we

describe this approach in general terms. From this description, it will become apparent that

limiting the perception of geometric properties to the domain of vision is more tradition than

necessity. Subsequent sections will address the lawfulness of acoustic structure that ought to

permit auditory perception of geometric properties. Finally, we summarize research that

documents listeners success.

The ecological approach to perception

The ecological approach to perception is a metatheory. As such, it describes a particular

conceptualization of how we can be aware of our surroundings. In general, metatheories endorse

a particular style of framing questions, promote certain strategies for addressing them, and seek

particular kinds of answers.1 The prevailing metatheory is that perception begins with inadequate

input, which becomes meaningful by virtue of internal computations. These computations permit

awareness of the world indirectly in the form of a mental representation. In contrast, the

ecological approach asserts that input, once properly construed, is rich and lawful and specific to

its source directly, without elaboration by internal mechanisms.

The properness of the construal is an important issue in revealing lawfulness and this

construal is what motivates the epithet ecological. Consider the form that a so-called ecological

law takes:

generates

event structured energy distribution.


specifies

1
Theories are consistent with these frameworks but aim at a more specific level, such as a theory of space
perception or a theory of movement perception.
Ecological acoustics

The inclusion of something as coarse-grained as an event highlights the ecological commitment

to discovering the appropriate level of description of an animal-environment setting. The object

undergoing some style of change is what structures the energy patterns that reach our perceptual

systems. Significantly, the object undergoing some style of change is also what is perceived. In

the place of the kinds of isolated sound properties that are the focus of traditional psychophysical

approaches, the source event and its properties are the focus of the ecological approach.

In the opening example, the bouncing bottle generates a particular acoustic pattern that is

specific to the event that gave rise to that pattern: a bouncing bottle. A breaking bottle or a

bouncing ball would generate different acoustic structure specific to those different events just as

those same events would generate distinct optical structure. In the domain of ecological

acoustics, our task is twofold: (1) to document the capabilities of perception on the basis of

sound, and (2) to identify what in the acoustic structure supports those capabilities. We can

expect to exploit successes in other perceptual systemsmost notably, vision and touchin

guiding our search for the relevant description. We are seeking invariants of energy distributions

that are generated lawfully by a particular event. These reliable patternings may well be

indifferent to the medium.2

Protocol studies and the possibilities of perceiving on the basis of sound

It is not uncommon for experimenters in a traditional psychoacoustics experiment to ask

2
We are endorsing the notion of amodal invariants: The same abstract invariant ought to characterize all of the
energy distributions structured by a given event. Some ecological psychologists consider invariants to be mode
specific, with different invariants in each type of energy distribution specific to the same event. Others argue for
intermodal invariants, a position that an event is specified by one emergent invariant that is defined over all energy
distributions. At the present time, the last of these is very difficult to assess experimentally.
Ecological acoustics

their listeners to match two tones on some low-level dimension such as loudness or pitch. Of

course, loudness is affected by the frequency of the tone as well as its amplitude; pitch is affected

by the amplitude as well as the frequency. From these carefully controlled studies, one generates

the classic equal loudness contours that show how perception is faulty in its ability to faithfully

register physical properties. Listeners in these experiments adopt what Gaver (1993a) has dubbed

a musical attitude. They are paying attention to the sounds as such with no concern for the

source event that produced them. Given that the source event is typically a tone generator, and

the sounds tend to be harmonic with a relatively simple development over time, they really have

no choice. But, of course, this bears little resemblance to how we are guided by hearing under

ordinary circumstance. Everyday sounds tend to be inharmonic, vary complexly over time and,

more than likely, vary along dimensions of pragmatic utility. Everyday listeners care about the

source of the sound, not the sound itself (Figure 1). They want to know what happened and what

it means for them (Gaver, 1993a; Schubert, 1975).

More in keeping with the style of everyday listening are so-called protocol studies.

Listeners are presented with a variety of recorded sounds and asked to identify what they hear.

long, wooden,
E dropped on a hard M
surface

loud,
low-pitched,
muddy

Figure 1. A pool cue drops to the floor and bounces repeatedly, generating a complex sound pattern. An everyday
listener (E) focuses on the properties of the source of the soundits size, material, and type of interaction. Most
psychoacoustics research asks participants to be musical listeners (M), focusing on the properties of the sound.
Ecological acoustics

They are generally quite successful at identifying footsteps, clapping, hammering, filing, tearing

paper, jangling keys, and so on (Gaver, 1988; Vanderveer, 1979). Protocol studies are, of course,

only a preliminary step in ecological acoustics because they permit no systematic control of

individual events and they make no demands of metrical precision on the part of the listener

(Gaver, 1993a). Nonetheless, two nice theoretical points are apparent. First, it is only when

listeners are unable to identify the source of a sound that they resort to reporting its sensory

aspects, in effect converting from everyday to musical listening. Second, listeners confusions

tend to be of events that have similar temporal profiles (e.g., hammering and stepping; filing and

scratching), pointing at the relevance of higher-order structure.3 Moreover, even without an

avenue for demonstrating metrical precision, some of the distinctions are, in fact, quite subtle

(e.g., listeners can distinguish ascending vs. descending stairs; Gaver, 1988). All of these suggest

that systematic physical analyses are possible and are needed.

Consider mechanical events. The vibration pattern in the air is influenced by the materials

involved in the event and the types of interactions those materials undergo (Gaver, 1993b). The

type of interaction, whether it is scraping or splashing or slapping, affects the time-varying

amplitude and the spectrum of vibration. The tension and elasticity of the materials are restoring

forces. The size, shape, and density of material determine its inertia. Both sets of factors

determine how quickly an object returns from the deformed state brought about by its interaction

with other objects or surfaces. This, in turn, determines the frequency of its vibrations. In brief,

3
Gaver (1988, 1993a) identified three broad categories of interactionsvibrating solids, aerodynamic sounds, and
liquid sounds. In his protocol studies, confusion remained within category. As he noted, they need not if the
temporal patterns of the events are similar (e.g., as illustrated in the use of tubes, pegs, and beads to simulate the
sound of rain in the so-called rain sticks of Mexico).
Ecological acoustics

sound is structured reliably by interacting materials. That is the rightward sequence of the

ecological law statement. The leftward sequencewhether this sound structure informs about

those materials and interactionsis the focus of experiments in ecological acoustics. What is the

object? What is it doing? Where is it doing it?

Categorical distinctions

Our choice of the example that begins this chapter was not accidental. The first experiment

to be labeled ecological acoustics was an examination of listeners ability to distinguish breaking

and bouncing events (Warren & Verbrugge, 1984). The first part of the study involved

categorizing natural sounds. Listeners were presented with tape recordings of various instances

of different sized bottles and jars falling to the ground and either breaking or bouncing. They

simply had to identify which event they heard (or whether they could not tell). The success rate

was 99%. The next step was to try to identify what in the sound structure might allow the

distinction to be made. As Figure 2 illustrates, the breaking event has an initial burst of noise.

Even when this burst was eliminated from the recording, however, listeners still achieved 96%

accuracy in the identification of breaking. What remained, of course, was the timing of the

Figure 2. (left) A bounce produces a single, damped, quasi-periodic pulse train


whereas (right) a break is characterized by an initial rupture or burst followed by
multiple, damped, quasi-periodic pulse trains.
Ecological acoustics

subsequent pulses. Artificial sound tokens were constructed, therefore, by means of manipulating

the timing of these pulses while leaving their spectral characteristics constant.

The construction of synthetic tokens began with pieces of a broken bottle. Four of the

largest pieces were dropped individually and recorded as they bounced. In one type of synthetic

token, the onsets of every impact of each of the four pieces were synchronized by inserting

appropriate amounts of silence between subsequent bounces so as to preserve the single,

damped, quasi-periodic pulse train that characterized bouncing. (Despite the presence of four

pieces, the synchrony supported the perception of a single object.) Sound events synthesized on

this basis were successfully identified as bouncing with 92% accuracy. Synthetic tokens

characterized only by a decline in the amplitude of the impacts without concomitant damping of

the temporal pattern (i.e., with the intervals equated between each of the bounces) were not heard

as bouncing. In a second type of synthetic token, the onsets of the four pieces were synchronized,

but then each followed a different damped, quasi-periodic pulse train. These were identified as

breaking with 87% accuracy (whether augmented by a noise burst or not).

The foregoing is an exemplary study in ecological acoustics. Although such a pedigree

makes it more likely that a researcher will be interested in source properties, a handful of more

traditionally oriented psychoacousticians have contributed to this literature. Two studies of

interest concern protocol events that listeners identified successfully: footsteps and clapping.

We already noted one subtlety of footsteps that listeners can pick up on: whether those

footsteps are going up the stairs or down. Given the different contributions of heel and toe strikes

to those two directions, this success is understandable. A possibly more subtle distinction, the

sex of the walker, can also be discerned simply on the basis of the sound of the walkers

footsteps (Li, Logan, & Pastore, 1991). Sixteen different walkers, eight of each sex wearing the
Ecological acoustics

same style shoe (low, solid synthetic heel), walked at their normal pace on a hardwood stage,

taking eight steps directly towards a microphone. Each of these strolls was recorded and a four-

step sequence from the middle was presented to listeners over headphones. The task was a

simple categorization as male or female. Males were identified correctly on 69% of the trials;

females were identified correctly on 75% of the trials. But there were substantial differences

within each gender category. Half of the males and half of the females were identified correctly

at least 85% of the time. Two more of the females were identified correctly at least 70% of the

time. But the remaining walkers were identified at no better than a chance level. A statistical

evaluation of various anthropometric measures indicated that walker height accounted for 70%

of the variance in the judgments of gender. The investigators conjectured that height was really

standing proxy for height of the center of mass, CM, which is known to differ for males and

females. Although they did not determine individuals CMs, we estimated them from

anthropometric standards and, indeed, these estimated CMs account for 76% of the variance in

judgments of gender. Spectral analyses suggested that male judgments were more likely when

the acoustics were characterized by more energy in the low frequency range with rapid spectral

rising and falling. Conversely, female judgments were more likely when the acoustics were

characterized by more energy in a higher frequency range with slow spectral rising and falling.

Clapping is another sound event that could be identified easily in a protocol study, but does

it allow listeners to discern anything about the clappers themselves? Twenty different clappers,

ten of each sex, were instructed to clap for 10 seconds at their normal rate, as they would

normally clap after an average concert or theater performance (Repp, 1987). Recordings were

presented to listeners over headphones, with the entire sequence being presented once for

familiarization before it was presented a second time for response collection. Since the
Ecological acoustics

10

individuals were all known to one another, the task was to label each bout of clapping as

belonging to one of the 20 people whose names appeared on an alphabetic list. Performance

(11% correct) was better than chance (5% correct) but it was not impressive. Self-recognition

was considerably better (46% correct) but, of course, that could have benefited from factors over

and above the acoustic specification of source properties.4 Even when re-scored simply for

whether a clapping bout was classified as having been produced by a male or female (even if the

specific identity was wrong), performance was only 54% (compared to a chance level of 50%;

Repp, 1987; see also Tousman & Pastore, 1989). Nonetheless, listeners performance was

systematic. A search of acoustic characteristics that encouraged the choice of a male or female

label revealed four factors that together accounted for 85% of the variance in judgments. Most

important was the contribution from the inter-clap interval: the slower the applause, the more

likely it was to be labeled male. Next in importance was the amplitude of the clapping: the louder

the clapping the more likely it was to be labeled male. The final factors are both spectral, with

the most intuitive interpretation being that low-frequency resonances were considered male.

None of these factors actually distinguished male and female clappers, which accounts for the

poor performance. But in a different sequence of claps, produced by a single person with

different hand configurations (palm-to-palm, finger-to-palm, or something in between), a new

group of listeners was successful in judging the configuration of the hands that produced the

clapping sequences.

Quantifying the mechanical properties of human effectorsthe legs of a walker, the hands

4
When the record of a movement is a visual trace (e.g., a trajectory of a figure-8 on a computer screen), people are
also better at identifying their own movements than identifying the movements of another (Prinz, 1997). Some
would like to understand that superiority with respect to a common code for perception and action.
Ecological acoustics

11

of a clapperthat give rise to particular acoustic properties is not straightforward. Moreover, the

sample of sound-producers may be idiosyncratic, either in physical dimensions (height and

weight combinations, hand sizes and shapes) or personal style of walking or clapping, that may

introduce variation that masks the dimension of interest. Finally, judgments of characteristics

such as the sex of the sound source may simply reflect general (and often erroneous) sex

stereotypes. Mechanical events, in contrast to biological events, allow more control over the

source characteristics with a consequent increase in the resolution that can be asked of

perceivers. But, in the modern idiom, if you dont ask, they dont tell. We turn next to

experiments that ask for modest performance on the part of listeners, rank-ordering sounds

without indicating their appreciation of relative differences.

Perceiving mechanical events on the basis of sound

We know that listeners can appreciate that a collision event did not entail breaking. Is

anything else known about the objects in the event? A variety of questions could be asked: What

were the materials, how large were the objects, were they solid or hollow? One such

investigation focused on percussive sound eventsa single impact of a mallet on a hollow

receptacle (Freed, 1990). Six mallets that varied in hardness were used to strike four receptacles

(cast aluminum cooking pans) that varied in size. The 24 percussive events were recorded in an

anechoic chamber and presented over a speaker. The guiding force was explicitly ecological, to

focus listeners on physical properties of the objectsthe mallets hardnessrather than abstract

properties of the soundwhether it is bright or dull, thin or full (cf. Lichte, 1941). Even with this

ecological goal, psychophysical timidity was nonetheless in evidence in the study. The sound

pressure level was roughly equalized across tokens, thereby restricting differences to spectral
Ecological acoustics

12

parameters. Each session began with a demonstration of the hardest mallet hitting first the

smallest pan and then the largest pan, followed by the softest mallet hitting the same two pans.

Listeners were told that these were instances of a hard and a soft mallet. The entire sequence of

sounds, which included four repetitions each of six mallets striking four different receptacles,

was then played once to familiarize listeners with the range of sounds. (The untutored

informativeness of the sounds was not strictly assessed.) Perceived mallet hardness was indicated

by continuously adjusting the length of a visible line segment on a scale marked from 1 to 9 for

softest to hardest. Harder mallets generally elicited higher ratings of hardness and seemed

unaffected by the pan that was struck. More germane for the interests of the investigator was the

identification of acoustic parameters that would be useful as predictors of timbre. A combination

of four spectral parameters characterizing the initial 325 ms of each event accounted for 75% of

the variance in hardness ratings. One is essentially a loudness measure (the log of the area under

the spectrum). Its slope represents the softening over time. A third reflects the brightness (the

mean of the centroid of the spectrum) and the fourth (the time-weighted average of the centroid

of the spectrum) represents the darkening over time.5

An inevitable implication of source-oriented auditory perception is that information about

an event is infused throughout the acoustic signal. Mechanical events involve the movements of

masses that are mutually constraining. How an event began influences how it can unfold; how it

is unfolding is informative about how it may have started. In principle, therefore, later-coming

acoustic structure can influence perception of an earlier event. This was the premise of an

5
Since these parameters are not invariant over resonators, they are unlikely candidates as the definitive constraints
on perceived mallet hardness, given that listeners mallet ratings were indifferent to what was struck (Lakatos,
McAdams, & Causs, 1997).
Ecological acoustics

13

investigation of the perception of steepness based on the sound of a ball rolling down a ramp

(Fowler, 1990). A steel ball was recorded rolling down five different ramps (10, 20, 30, 40 and

50 deg) onto either a flat track or an upward sloping track. During such events, the time that the

ball spends on the track is determined by the slant of the initial ramp, but in opposite ways for

the two tracks. On a flat track, a longer duration means that the early part of the event was

shallower; on an up-slope, a longer duration means that the early part of the event was steeper

(Figure 3). The experimental sequences were hybrid stimuli constructed by splicing acoustic

signals from the extremes of the track portions onto acoustic signals from each ramp slope. That

is, for a given ramp the track portion was replaced by four options: the flat and the upward slope

that had accompanied the 10 and the 50 ramps. If the later-coming acoustic structure influences

perception of an earlier event, then listeners judging the slant of the ramp ought to be influenced

by the track portions they hear and in specific ways. For the up-sloped tracks, the shorter

duration track sounds ought to yield flatter perceived ramp slopes than longer duration track

sounds. For the flat tracks, shorter track portions ought to yield steeper perceived ramp slopes

than longer track portions. In other words, duration per se is not the critical acoustic structure.

a c

b d

Figure 3. (a) Initial ramps of different slopes will influence the length of time a ball bearing
spends on a flat track before falling off. (b) The time on the track is longer the flatter the initial
ramp. (c) When the track slopes upward, the ball slows before rolling back down. (d) The time
on the track is shorter the flatter the initial slope.
Ecological acoustics

14

Prior to the experimental test, listeners were presented with recordings of just the ramp

portions from the 10 and 50 ramps five times in alternation and told which was which. They

were instructed that in the test, they would hear the entire rolling event and they were to judge

whether the ramp portion was steep or flat. Ten listeners heard the ramps spliced onto the flat

tracks and another ten listeners heard the ramps spliced onto the up-slopes. Ramps were

generally ordered appropriately in all conditions, even though the track portions did not help this

specific discrimination. More importantly, the track portions did produce the expected

interaction. Listeners in the flat-track condition heard all ramps as steeper if they had been

spliced to a short duration track portion; listeners in the sloped-track condition heard all ramps as

steeper if they had been spliced to a long duration track portion. A subsequent experiment,

limited to the flat-track condition, addressed the duration issue directly. A track portion from the

10 ramp was cut at regular intervals until it was equal in duration to the 50 portion (it was

essentially halved). Ramps appended to this shortened track portion were indeed heard as steeper

than those with the original long, 10 flat track but not as steep as those with the original 50

track. In other words, duration is not the only dimension that is informative about ramp slope.

Still audible, for example, was the balls revolution speed.

The upshot of this research is the emphasis on perceiving the source event. Had conditions

been limited to the flat tracks, one might infer that listeners are simply influenced by a general

auditory cue, durational contrast. The opposite durational pattern from the upward sloping track

instead supports the notion that listeners recover physical event properties from the information

available in acoustic structure.

Both the mallet hardness and the ramp slant studies show that listeners perceive properties

of environmental objects and surfaces with some degree of gradation: mallets are more or less
Ecological acoustics

15

hard, ramps are more or less slanted. However, neither the mallet nor the slope investigations

exploited a specific advantage of mechanical events. Metrical precision of perception, not just

rank-ordering, can be assessed. That is to say, perceived increments in a dimension of interest

can be evaluated relative to physical increments in that dimension. This has been the focus of

recent investigations of shape and size perception on the basis of sound.

A first step toward metrical precision in perceiving mechanical events

The in-principle argument for specification is straightforward. To the extent that an event

structures sound reliably, that structure ought to specify the source event. But what provides the

metric? Characteristic modes of vibration are one possibility. Objects with a high degree of

symmetry, for example, have three orthogonal modes (Figure 4) that are determined by the

physical dimensions (size, shape) and material properties (mass, density, elasticity) of the source.

An object set into vibration will conform to one of its characteristic modes despite variation in

pitch and timbre (Lakatos et al., 1997). The relative contribution of each mode, however,

depends on how an object is struck. This so-called exciter-resonator relationship is often

nonlinear (Fletcher & Rossing, 1991). Consequently, one methodological strategy is to keep the

strike position constant while varying spatial dimensions of the resonating object.

In one such investigation (Lakatos et al., 1997), the objects were long bars made of steel or

a b c

Figure 4. A metal bar tends to vibrate (a) transversely, (b) longitudinally,


and (c) torsionally. The modes of vibration of are orthogonal.
Ecological acoustics

16

wood, suspended lengthwise and struck at the center with a mallet (steel for the steel bars, resin

for the wooden bars). The bars were of a fixed length but varied in thickness and width; bar

girth is what listeners had to discern (the specific dimensions differed for the two materials).

Sound recordings were made in an anechoic chamber, and matched for loudness. Multiple

recordings were made so that only clear samples were selected. During the experiment, sounds

were presented over a speaker in a sound-isolation booth. A trial consisted of a pair of sounds, in

succession, accompanied by two response alternatives presented visually. These alternatives

represented the actual cross-sectional proportions of the bars (scaled to the computer screen), but

in both the correct and the incorrect order. Listeners had to choose which order corresponded to

the order of the sounds they heard (20 practice trials without feedback familiarized them with

this so-called two-alternative forced-choice, or 2AFC, procedure). Prior to the practice trials,

listeners were allowed to strike five sample bars (not from the experiment set) with the

appropriate mallet to familiarize themselves with the type of interaction they would be hearing.

Finally, they were told to use any available timbral cues to make their decision.

Listeners who failed to attain a 75% performance criterion were excluded from the analysis

(out of the original 60 listeners, 5 did not reach criterion for the steel bars and 10 did not reach

criterion for the wooden bars). With these exclusions, listeners performance did indeed vary

with differences in the width to height ratios and improved the greater those differences were.

For metal bars, the more block-like cross-sections tended to cluster together as did the more

plate-like cross-sections. This pattern was not evident for the wooden bars, which listeners found

harder to discriminate (perhaps because the signals were so much shorter). Acoustic analyses

indicated that matching performance correlated strongly with the frequencies of the vibration

modes. In particular, for metal bars, the frequencies of the torsional modes, FT, accounted for
Ecological acoustics

17

86% of the variance in listener responses. As an alternative, the ratio of the transverse bending

modes dependent on width to those dependent on height, FW/ FH, accounted for 88% of the

variance. These relationships were less secure for the wooden bars, not only because the variance

accounted for was less (58% by with FT; 67% by FW/ FH) but also because those components are

sometimes quite weak or absent in those bars. No attempt was made to provide a comprehensive

account of performance with both sets of bars (Lakatos et al., 1997). One problem is that wood is

an orthotropic material (Rossing & Fletcher, 1995); its mechanical properties, unlike metals,

tend to vary along three perpendicular axes.

At some level, the preceding illustrates a finer degree of resolution on the part of listeners.

They were asked to discriminate the cross-sectional shapes of struck bars whose width-height

ratios ranged from .13 to 1.00. Given the 2AFC procedure, however, we only know that listeners

could discriminate different shaped rods, and that discrimination was easier the more different

the rods were. But we have no appreciation for listeners accuracy in perceiving the rods. In the

absence of the visual matches, could they have indicated that one rod was block-like and another

was plate-like? They reached a performance criterion of 75%, but that was after poor listeners

were eliminated. Given the precision in the sound recordingsanechoic chambers eliminate

reverberation, loudness is equalized, only clear recordings are usedshould we be impressed

with listener achievement? How would listeners fare if the sounds came from real objects in an

ordinary room? What if they were provided with some leeway in responding? Do they actually

need all of the practice and restrictions that characterize the research considered so far?

Metrical precision in perceiving struck plates

We have been building a case, at least implicitly, that by the very nature of the research
Ecological acoustics

18

questions asked in auditory experiments, the science of perception doubts the fine-grained spatial

capabilities of hearing. Consider this opinion from Sir Arthur Schuster in 1882, who was

illustrating the challenge to be faced by the then-new science of spectroscopy:

To find out the different tunes sent out by a vibrating system is a problem which may or may not
be solvable in certain special cases, but it would baffle the most skillful mathematician to solve the
inverse problem and to find out the shape of a bell by means of the sounds which it is capable of
sending out (cf. Gordon & Webb, 1996).

Mathematicians generally endorse this skepticism. Kac (1966) posed the question explicitly:

Can one hear the shape of a drum? and it has been answered explicitly, You cant hear the

shape of a drum (Gordon & Webb, 1996). Isospectral companionsidentical spectra produced

by two manifolds that differ geometricallyare to blame. But, of course, mathematicians

operate in idealized space. Just because isospectral companions are possible need not mean that

they are representative or problematic. First, they seem to be the exception (Gordon & Webb,

1996). Second, trying to implement such manifolds with real physical objects would likely

introduce differences, however small, in their physical parameters (Kunkler-Peck & Turvey,

2000). What happens if we ask the shape question of perceivers rather than mathematicians?

The drums were, in fact, flat steel plates (circle, square, and triangle) struck by a steel

pendulum bob released from a fixed location so that it would always impart the same amount of

energy (Kunkler-Peck & Turvey, 2000; Figure 5a). The plates, which had the same mass and

surface area, were simply suspended by fishing line to provide stability with minimal damping

and without eliciting vibration in the support structure. A listener sat on one side of a screen that

hid the shape that was being struck (about 1 m on the other side). On each trial, the bob was

released from the starting location and caught right after it bounced off the plate. This was

repeated three times so that a trial was defined by three strikes. Each of the three objects, was
Ecological acoustics

19

a b c

H W
Dimension
Figure 5. (a) A simply suspended plate is struck by a pendulum bob. (b) A listener whose view is occluded,
adjusts dowels to indicate the height or width. (c) Proportional shape is distinguished.

presented three times in random order. Listeners had to indicate verbally which plate had been

struck, with no prior demonstrations of the sounds and no practice trials. Nonetheless, the correct

shape was chosen 58% of the time (where chance performance would have been 33%).

To make the task a little harder, a further experiment included the same three shapes in

wood and Plexiglas as well as steel, again with dimensions chosen to provide the same surface

area (mass differed across material but was the same for the three shapes of a given material).

Because listeners were asked about the material as well, the verbal response was replaced by

having them point at replicas of the nine objects mounted on the occlusion screen. Once again,

there were no demonstrations or practice trials. Perceiving material was absolutely

straightforward; one of the seven listeners made one misidentification. Shape performance was

comparable to the previous experiment. The correct shape was chosen 56% of the time (where

chance performance on shape again would have been 33%). Moreover, there were no systematic

confusions in the errors. This suggests that circles, squares, and triangles really sounded like

circles, squares, and triangles rather than simply being labeled by a strategy that could be

consistently wrong.
Ecological acoustics

20

The shape experiment demonstrates a degree of geometric sensitivity. With real sounds in

an ordinary room, listeners identified shape reliably. Their responses were constrained, of course,

by the shape categories provided, thereby limiting how wrong they could be. A truly metrical

response would provide a stronger test. In order to remain in the realm of perceiving shape, this

time the steel plates were all rectangles but of different proportions: a square (48.2 48.2 cm), a

medium rectangle (38.1 61.0 cm), and a long rectangle (25.4 91.4 cm). Again, dimensions

were chosen so that the plates were equal in mass and surface area. The occlusion screen was

augmented with a response apparatus that allowed a listener to provide a visual match for a

plates height independently of its width (Figure 5b). The width indicator ranged from 0 to

2.5 m; the height indicator ranged from 0 to 1.5 m. As before, there were no demonstrations or

practice and this time there was no information about the number of objects. Additionally, there

was no indication of the sizes of the objects (other than the 2.5 1.5 m maximum allowed by the

apparatus). On a given trial, the listener was told which dimension to report before the plate was

struck. He or she adjusted the appropriate indicator to provide a visual match for the heard height

or width. Each of the three rectangles was presented six times (three for width, three for height).

The actual linear dimensions accounted for 98% of the variance in listeners responses.

Although perceived dimensions were underestimates of actual dimensions (ranging from 25.2 cm

to 44.5 cm for an actual range from 25.4 cm to 91.4 cm), they were in the approximate range. We

refer to this as definite scaling rather than as relative scaling (Bingham, 1993; Turvey & Carello,

1995) because responses are more than simply ordered, arbitrary magnitudes. They do not use

the entire range, nor do they use either extreme of the range. Listeners appear to have a definite

impression of size (indeed, the average reliability of their responses was 6%, which compares

favorably to the visual impression of size; cf. Norman, Todd, Perotti, & Tittle, 1996). Most
Ecological acoustics

21

impressive is their sensitivity to shape (Figure 5c). When they attended to the height of the

rectangles, their responses were larger than when they attended to the widths of those same

rectangles. For the squares, those reports were the same.

Before addressing the acoustic support for this performance, lets consider one more

demand placed on the listeners. The preceding experiment was replicated with the three

rectangular shapes cut from wood and Plexiglas as well as steel. As before, all plates had the

same surface area; plates of the same material had the same mass. As before, listeners positioned

the report apparatus to indicate the dimension requested on a given trial. As before, perceived

dimensions (23.5 cm to 51.4 cm) were in the approximate range of actual dimensions (25.4 cm to

91.6 cm) with a mean reliability of 5.5%.

The simple support of the plates means that their vibrational dynamics are captured by the

two-dimensional wave equation (Rossing & Fletcher, 1995). The frequencies associated with the

solutions to that equation are given by

mn = 0.453 h E m+12 + n+12 (1)


(1 2) Lx Ly

where h is the thickness of the plate, E is Youngs modulus, is the mass density, is Poissons

ratio, m and n are integers indexing the vibratory modes, Lx is width, and Ly is height. Obviously,

the modal frequencies are influenced by more than the plates linear dimensions. The physical

parameters constrain how the plate bends (Figure 4). This is the hypothesized informational

support for perceived dimension. It accounted for 87% of the variance in perceived dimension in

the preceding experiment. Note that asking a listener to report height or width is asking that

listener to perceive selectively. Out of the flux of stimulation, they are to extract just that

structure relevant to the requested dimension. Analytically, this selectivity was captured by
Ecological acoustics

22

calculating mn with m = 0 for one dimension and n = 0 for the other. While this works quite well

as a way of summarizing data, we really dont understand what it would mean for the listener to

do the same thing functionally.

Metrical precision in perceiving the lengths of dropped rods

The clean strike of a supported object (or a sequence of such strikes) allows sound structure

that is simpler than that normally encountered in everyday listening. The experimental rationale

is that the scientist needs to know whats in the sound in order to determine what listeners can

respond to. A different strategyinspired by the distinction between everyday listening and

musical listeningis to give listeners as much structure as they ordinarily encounter in everyday

events with acoustic consequences. Apart from the dinner gong, not many sounds are simple

strikes. Objects fall to the floor, they clatter and bounce and roll to a stop, with the sound

reverberating in the room. Listeners have access to all of that in ordinary experience so lets give

them access to all of that in the experiment. Once we assess how metrically precise listeners can

be, then we can worry about how to quantify the available structure.

This was the premise of experiments in which listeners were asked to indicate the lengths

of cylindrical rods that fell to the floor (Carello, Anderson, & Kunkler-Peck, 1998). In one

experiment, wooden dowels 1.25 cm in diameter were cut in lengths from 30 cm to 120 cm (in

15 cm increments). In a second experiment (with different listeners), the diameters were .32 cm

and the lengths ranged from 10 to 40 cm (in 5 cm increments). On a trial, a rod was dropped five

times in succession. To standardize the drop as much as possible, a rod was balanced at its center

of mass on a support 72 cm above a hard linoleum surface. The turn of a handle allowed the rod

to fall from a fixed height. Listeners sat at a student desk on the other side of an occlusion screen
Ecological acoustics

23

Perceived Length (cm)


120
r2 = 0.97
90

60

30

0
0 30 60 90 120
Actual Lengh (cm)
Figure 6. (a) A listener adjusted the position of a report board to indicate the length of a rod that had dropped
on the other side of an occlusion screen. The rod was released from a support stand by the turn of a small
lever. (b) Length was perceived with surprising accuracy (perfect performance is indicated by the dashed line)
even though listeners were unaware of the number of rods or their possible lengths.

in front of a response apparatus that allowed them to position a marker anywhere from 0 to 2 m

to coincide with how far they could reach with the rod (Figure 6a). They were provided no

practice and no information about the number or sizes of the rods; they simply listened.

For the large rods, perceived lengths ranged from 24 to 95 cm. Actual length accounted for

95% of the variance in perceived length. For the small rods, perceived lengths ranged from 14 to

27 cm. Actual length accounted for 95% of the variance in perceived length. The slopes of the

perceived-actual functions were different for the two rod sizes, with the discrimination being

sharper for large rods (slope = .78) than for small rods (slope = .44). Nonetheless, the two data

sets in combination provided a strong dependence of perceived length on actual length (an

overall slope of .77 with 97% of the variance accounted for; Figure 6b).6

For the acoustic analyses, the sounds were recorded from the listeners position under the

6
With somewhat less success, Gaver (1988) asked listeners to indicate the lengths of bars, made of iron or oak, that
were struck once at their centers sitting on a carpeted floor when struck. The sounds were recorded and played to
listeners over headphones. Not all listeners discriminated length and they were differentially affected by material.
The fidelity of the recordings may be at fault, along with the less informative impact events.
Ecological acoustics

24

same conditions as described in the foregoing with the exception that a given rod was dropped

only three times. One might think that a simple acoustic variable, something that relates to length

straightforwardly, ought to account for performance. But neither the duration of the signal, its

average amplitude, nor its frequency centroid approached the success of actual length in

constraining performance. Average amplitude fared best, accounting for 70% of the overall

variance but it fared less well on the set of large rods (21%). Frequency centroid accounted for

66% of the overall variance but less for the individual sets (59 % and 37% for the large and small

rods, respectively). Signal duration accommodated the large rods better than the small (65% vs.

12% of the variance) but overall, it accounted for only 9% of the variance in listener responses.

Although actual length predicts perceived length successfully, it cannot be the constraining

variable. Length is a geometric property, not the kind of mechanical property that can affect

acoustic structure. Its success in the preceding experiments was because the rods of different

diameters were also in non-overlapping length ranges. When this is no longer so, actual length is

not a good predictor of perceived length (Anderson, Carello, & Kunkler-Peck, 1996). Using the

same experimental procedure as in the foregoing, listeners judged five rod lengths cut from

dowels of three different diameters. Perceived length increased with increases in actual length

but the latter accounted for only 39% of the variance in overall responses. Similarly, when rod

lengths are fashioned from different materials (steel, Plexiglas, and wood), actual length

accounts for only 18% of the variance in perceived length.

Manipulations of length, diameter, and material density are simply different ways of

manipulating a higher-order property, an objects mass distribution. This property is quantified

through the inertia tensor, essentially, the resistances of an object to being rotated in different

directions. As noted earlier, inertia influences the vibratory pattern in an impact event and, as
Ecological acoustics

25

such, provides a sensible candidate for the mechanical constraint on perceived length by hearing.

Not surprisingly, rods inertia tensors account for nearly all of the variance in perceived length in

the initial experiments with large and small rods and 91% of the variance in the diameter

experiments. Manipulations of material provide an interesting case, however. Material density

has consequences for the inertia tensor, to be sure, but it also is related to elasticity and stiffness

which, in turn, have consequences for how a body returns to an equilibrium state after being

displaced by an external forcing function (such as accompanies dropping to a surface). Indeed,

the rods inertia tensors alone do not predict perceived length of rods of different densities. But

when augmented by Youngs modulus of elasticity, the variance accounted for is 96%.7

As a matter of pedagogical convenience, we have been characterizing the achievements of

listeners with respect to perceiving particular properties of objects (e.g., length, shape, slant) or

types of interactions (e.g., jangling, bouncing, dropping). In its focus on awareness of the source

rather than awareness of the sensations, this emphasis has illustrated a central concern of the

ecological approach. But it is incomplete. Perceptions raison dtre is guiding activity.

Perceivers need to be aware of objects and events because of the consequences for what

perceivers-as-actors can do. From the perspective of ecological psychology, perception is not

awareness of objects and events per se but awareness of their behavioral relevance. Such

opportunities for behavior are what Gibson (1979, 1983) termed affordances. Behavioral

possibilities are central to a good deal of acoustic research to which we now turn.

7
The relevance of the inertia tensor to the perception of length has long been appreciated for dynamic touch (cf.
Turvey, 1996), work which inspired the dropped rods experiments. And the inspiration goes both ways. The inertia
tensor completely constrains perceived length when wielded objects vary in diameter and density (Fitzpatrick,
Carello, & Turvey, 1994), but elasticity is a constraint when the objects are nonrigid (GrandPre & Carello, 2001).
Ecological acoustics

26

Affordances: Perceiving behavioral possibilities

We have already introduced the notion of affordance indirectly in the rod dropping

experiments. Listeners were not asked to provide a report of length in units of inches or

centimeters. Instead, they were asked to position the visible report surface to coincide with how

far they could reach with the rod they had heard. Reconceptualizing absolute geometric

properties such as length in terms of activity-relevant properties such as reach-with-able is a

goal of ecological theory. An affordance is a legitimate occupant of the left slot in the ecological

law statement. Such a reconceptualization is ultimately a goal of ecological research as well. But

fulfilling that goal requires that we formally fill the right slot in the ecological law statement as it

pertains to a particular affordance. What pattern of structure in an ambient energy array is

specific to an affordance such as reachable? Reachable is a very different kind of thing from

length. We know how to measure length; we have to discover how to measure reachable.

Ecological psychologists are faced with the very real possibility that the currently available

scientific toolkit is not up to the job of quantifying information specific to affordances. In the

meantime, a good deal of the discovery process involves identifying the variety of affordances

that are perceived and the kinds of manipulations that affect them. Oftentimes, the targeted

affordances have already been investigated in the visual domain and the hope is that finding

commonalities will give us a foothold on identifying the information. And heres why. We are

seeking invariants of structured energy distributions, patterns that are always produced by a

given affordance regardless of incidental details that can give rise to dramatically different

sensations. An objects shape and material surely matter to the intensities and wavelengths of

reflected light that reach the eye but they do not matter to whether you can reach that object.

Instead, we seek some invariant of structured light specific to whether something is reachable or
Ecological acoustics

27

not. And, on extension, whether an object structures light or compression waves is also irrelevant

to whether you can reach it. We might, therefore, seek a higher-order pattern common to both

ambient energy arrays that is lawfully related to what is reachable (see FN 1).

A key issue is one of prospective control (e.g., Turvey, 1992; E. J. Gibson, 1994). Your

actions are organized in such a way that you can effect certain outcomes. For example, picking

up a pencil from the desk does not begin with your throwing an arm out in its general direction

and hoping for the best. You can see that the pencil is within reach with an outstretched arm or

that it will require an additional bend at the hip. Indeed, examinations of this visual ability have

shown that sensitivity to the boundary of reach is body-scaled, that is, it is the same for tall and

short reachers (with correspondingly long and short arms), once the boundary is scaled to the

appropriate effector (Carello, Grosofsky, Reichel, Solomon, & Turvey, 1989). But if that same

pencil rolled off the desk out of view, could we hear whether it dropped within reach?

Developmental data clearly support the salience of hearing what is reachable in that infants

reach more often for a sound source in the dark when that sound source is within reach than

when it is out of reach (Clifton, Perris, & Bullinger, 1991; Perris & Clifton, 1988). Formal

auditory reaching experiments were modeled after those in vision. Listeners were selected to be

tall or short. The sound-emitting target, a kind of rattle, was placed at different distances from

the listeners (Figure 7a). When the reach was to be with an arm outstretched from the shoulder,

distances ranged from 38 to 110 cm, in 8 cm increments. When the reach was to be with the

outstretched arm augmented by a bend at the hip, distances ranged from 75 to 150 cm, also in 8

cm increments. There were three repetitions of each distance within each type of reach, and each

block began with 10 practice trials. During a trial, listeners simply judged whether the rattle was

within reach. No actual reaches were conducted until after all judgments were collected, when
Ecological acoustics

28

a b 100 c 100

% Reachable
% Reachable
75 75
50 50
25 25
0 0
30 50 70 90 110 0.5 1.0 1.5
Distance (cm) Distance/Arm
Figure 7. (a) A blind folded listener judges whether the rattle is within reach. (b) Short listeners (open circles)
cannot reach as far as tall listeners (filled circles). (c) When target distance is scaled by the appropriate effector,
judgments by tall and short listeners do not differ.

the actual maximum reaches in the two conditions were obtained. In all respects, the results

rivaled or exceeded those from vision. Whereas visual judgments tended to be overestimates

(Carello et al., 1989), auditory judgments of maximum reach did not differ from actual

maximum reach (Rosenblum, Wuestefeld, & Anderson, 1996). As would be expected, tall

reachers had a farther reaching boundary than short reachers (Figure 7b), but these boundaries

were the same when scaled intrinsically (Figure 7c).

Attempts to characterize the informational support for auditory perception of reachability

implicate a higher-order combination of sound intensity and the ratio of direct-to-indirect sound

reaching the listener (Wightman & Jenison, 1995). But these simply address distance-relevant

structure. The key to perceiving what is reachable must address the body-scaling. How do I

know that rattle is reachable by me? One intriguing conjecture received modest experimental

support. Judgments of what is reachable were less consistent (though no less accurate) when

acoustic structure was restricted to one ear (with the other ear being substantially muffled).

Given the allometric relationship between inter-aural distance (i.e., cranium size) and arm length

(Snyder et al., 1974), binaural superiority suggests the possibility of an intrinsic metric in

acoustic structure that, in effect, scales what is reachable for the listener (Rosenblum,
Ecological acoustics

29

Wuestefeld, & Anderson, 1996). An analogous intrinsic metric in visual structure, inter-ocular

distance, has been promoted as serving a similar function for optically specified reaches in the

preying mantis (Michaels, Prindle, & Turvey, 1985) and distance perception, in general, for

humans (Michaels, 1986).

Just as questions of perceiving what is reachable ecologize the problem of distance

perception, other issues of space perception can be made similarly functional. Consider the

question of localizing a sound source, one of the few routinely source-oriented classical

questions. In classical hands, it is simply a question of the distance and direction to a sound-

emitting object. But a sound-source does not sit in isolation. It is found, for example, among

surfaces that reflect its sound.8 Its relation to these other surfaces may have consequences for

behavior. For affordance-minded researchers, one consequence that has been addressed

experimentally is whether the gap between the sound source and a vertical surface would allow

the listener-as-walker to pass through. A recording of a complex sound, the assembly call of a

mallard duck, was played through a loudspeaker that faced a side wall in a long room. The

speaker, which was at ear-height, was placed at 12 distances ranging from 20 to 75 cm from the

wall. The listener stood with eyes closed, one shoulder next to the wall 2 m from the aperture

and, on a given trial, judged whether he or she could walk through the gap between the sound

and the wall. For all eight listeners, narrow gaps were heard as not allowing passage, wide gaps

were heard as allowing passage (Figure 8a) and, as is standard in these kinds of experiments,

variability in judgments was greatest around the transition from passable to not passable (Russell

8
Our discussion is limited to situations involving direct sounds. A considerable literature addresses the perception of
surface layout on the basis of echolocation, in which the listeners use reflections of self-produced sounds (e.g.,
footfalls, cane taps, spoken syllables). An ecological treatment can be found in Stoffregen & Pittenger, 1995).
Ecological acoustics

30

& Turvey, 1999; cf. Fitzpatrick, Carello, Schmidt,


100
a b
80 & Corey, 1994). This transition occurred at 1.11
% Yes

60 times the listeners shoulder width which


40
compares favorably with the value of 1.16
20 E1
E2 obtained with similar work with visual apertures
0
0 20 40 60 80 100 120 140
Distance (cm) (Warren & Whang, 1987).
Figure 8. (a) Judgments of whether an aperture
could be walked through are categorical. (b) Since the right shoulder was adjacent to the
When the sound source and listener are shifted so
that all gaps are passable, the percentage of wall, listeners may have been aware of the walls
passable responses increases although the pattern
is still somewhat categorical. location not by reflected sound but by touching

the wall with that shoulder during ordinary

postural sway. Judging what allowed passage, then, would simply be a matter of locating the

sound source to the left of the left shoulder, perhaps constrained by a certain magnitude of

azimuth. To address this possibility, the sound source and listener were positioned 60 cm away

from the wall. The relationship between the speaker and the sound source remained the same, but

all apertures were, in fact, passable. Judgments based on body-scaled information about gap size

should have been 100% passable; judgments based on the location of the speaker relative to the

left shoulder should simply have shifted the category boundary rightward. Figure 8b shows that

performance by a new group of eight listeners was reasonably categorical with the boundary

shifted to the right. However, listeners were much more likely to judge gaps as passable in

Experiment 2 (70% of the time compared to 40% in Experiment 1), suggesting some body-

scaling. The remaining categorical pattern may reflect a methodological quirk: Listeners may

have found it difficult to say yes on every trial. Clearly, unlike Experiment 1, there were no

apertures that were judged not passable all of the time.


Ecological acoustics

31

A more straightforward test of the azimuthal hypothesis was provided by locating the

aperture at three distances from the listener. If a gap is judged passable when the sound source

exceeds a certain magnitude of azimuth, then closer gaps ought to be judged more passable than

farther gaps. However, performance was equivalent with the aperture at 1 m and 2 m; it

deteriorated completely with the aperture at 3 m. Minimally, this result suggests that listeners

were not using the azimuthal direction of the sound source. Interestingly, listeners who had seen

the spatial layout of the room before beginning the experiment produced a cleaner category

boundary than those who were led into the room with their eyes already closed. That is, they saw

the size of the room and where they would be standing (but not where the speaker would be).

This suggests that the scaling of perception on the basis of sound is very abstract indeed.

Although obviously ecological in context, these kinds of affordance experiments may

encourage participants to be too analytic (Heft, 1993). If listeners dwell on what the

experimenter wants them to do, they may try to elect a conscious strategy to satisfy those

demands (recall the problem of stereotypes in perceiving the sex of a walker or clapper). The

analytic attitude, in some sense, undermines their naturalness in detecting the appropriate

information. When participants are hurried or less focused on explicit judgments they are, in fact,

more accurate (Heft, 1993). Making the perceptual task part of an on-going activity would be the

ideal situation from a theoretical as well as methodological perspective. This is easier to achieve

in the realm of interceptive behaviors, to which we now turn.

Acoustic information about impending collisions

Perceiving time to contact in the visual domain has been a topic of much investigation (for

reviews, see Lee, 1980, 1990; Tresilian, 1993). The basic premise is that, given a collision course
Ecological acoustics

32

between a perceiver and a surface, the perceiver needs to see when the surface will be reached

before the collision actually occurs. This is so whether the perceiver is moving towards a surface

or a surface is moving towards the perceiver. A single event illustrates both of these. A base

runner-as-perceiver churns towards the catcher-as-upcoming surface; the catcher-as-perceiver

prepares to make the tag on that runner-as-upcoming-surface. In the simplest case of rectilinear

forward motion with constant velocity, the perceiver who would control that collision

prospectively needs to know, If current conditions persist, when will contact occur?

The optical variable that specifies time to contact (under conditions of constant velocity

and rectilinear motion) is a quantity, termed (Lee, 1976, 1980), which is given by the inverse of

the relative rate of dilation of an optical angle. In the preceding example, an optical angle defined

with the catcher as its base and the runners point of observation as its apex expands as the

runner gets closer to the catcher (Figure 9a). That angle increases gradually while the runner is

still far away but virtually explodes when contact is imminent (Figure 9b). Lee (1990) has argued

that is quite general and applies to any time-varying array variable. This includes other aspects

of optical structure (e.g., the relative rate of constriction of an optical gap might specify contact

between two objects; Bootsma & Oudejans, 1993) as well as any of a variety of acoustic array

a b
Time to Contact (s)

100 0
t1 t2
Angle(deg)

75
-2
50
-4
25
0 -6
0 25 50 75 100
Distance (ft)
Figure 9. (a) As a base runner approaches the catcher, the optical angle subtended by the catcher expands.
(b) The expansion (circles) changes most dramatically right before contact. For constant velocity, time to
contact changes at a constant rate (pluses).
Ecological acoustics

33

variables that change over time as a sound source nears a listener. For example, as a sound

source approaches from the right, its loudness increases, its pitch rises in a pattern known as the

Doppler shift, and the onset of sound at the right ear precedes the onset at the left ear.

The amplitude changes are most like the traditional understanding of optical . Indeed, a

formal derivation of acoustic for rectilinear approach verifies an intensity-based structure

specific to time to contact (Shaw, McGowan, & Turvey, 1991):

acoustic = 2I/dIdt (2)

where I is given by the inverse square law and velocity is constant. Plots of intensity changes

during approach to a sound source look very much like Figure 9b. A variation on this theme has

also been derived for pass-by: the negative of the intensity relative to the time derivative of

intensity (Erwin, 1995).

This means that acoustic structure specific to time to contact exists. But can listeners use it?

Some listeners, at least, can perceive time to contact by ear as well as observers judge it by eye.

Blind adults listened to the sound tracks of filmed events that sighted adults viewed: approach

trajectories (either direct or near-misses less than 5 from midline) of 12 vehicles and 2 people

filmed at varying speeds (Schiff & Oldak, 1990). Vehicle sounds included engine and tire noises;

people sounds were primarily continuous talking. Film clips lasted from 4 to 6 sec after which

the approaching sound source vanished 1.5 to 6.5 sec before it would have reached the plane of

the participants shoulders. Participants pressed a key to indicate when the vehicle or walker

would have reached them had it continued at the same speed. Six congenitally or early-blind

adult listeners performed a least as well on the audio-alone sequences as did 20 sighted observers

on the video-alone portions (the small sample size of blind participants precluded a statistical

evaluation). Performance by both groups deteriorated for long times-to-arrival.


Ecological acoustics

34

Two more groups of sighted observers (20 in each condition) listened to the audio alone or

were presented with the complete audio + video sequences. During those first 3-4 sec, their

performance did not differ from their video-alone counterparts nor did the combination of audio

and video improve performance (and all were underestimates). These groups also experienced

more difficulty for long times-to-arrival, with the deterioration being especially dramatic for the

audio-alone, sighted listeners. Not surprisingly, kinematic analyses of acoustic structure (and,

apparently, optical structure as well) for events in this velocity range indicate little differentiation

in intensity, Doppler, or inter-aural patterns beyond 3 sec (Wightman & Jenison, 1995). In other

words, listeners and observers have difficulty in a range where the available structure is not

informative. It could be argued that this range is beyond the need for fine-grained prospective

control (e.g., Shaw et al., 1991). Alternatively, one could take the perspective that the acoustical

structure in question, while not appropriate for the timing of interceptive behavior, is appropriate

for orienting the perceiver toward the approaching object (Guski, 1992). When appropriately

oriented, the optical can then be adaptively exploited. The preceding orienting hypothesis

highlights that audition and vision, like all perceptual systems, are typically used together. In the

setting under discussion, vision and audition coordinate in localizing an object and determining

time to arrival (Guski, 1992).

The preceding results suggest that when contact is less than 4 sec away, acoustic structure

is equivalent to optical structure in specifying time to contact. A finer scaling might be provided,

however, by an auditory analog of a standard visual experiment that asks observers to decide

which of two approaching objects would hit them first. When the objects are computer

simulations of approaching squares, viewers achieve a 75% success criterion as long as the

arrival times of the two objects differ by at least 50 msec (Todd, 1981). When the simulations are
Ecological acoustics

35

of two sounds approaching a listener, one from the left and one from the right, preliminary data

indicate that the 75% criterion is achieved as long as the arrival time differs by at least 300 msec

(Wightman & Jenison, 1995).

The kinematic analyses by Wightman and Jenison (1995) show less dramatic changes for a

transverse trajectory compared to oblique trajectories. We might expect listeners to have even

more difficulties in such situations. The contribution of intensity, Doppler, and interaural

patterns to perceiving pass-by on a transverse trajectory has been examined experimentally with

a simulated European ambulance siren presented over earphones (Rosenblum, Carello, &

Pastore, 1987). These variables change coherently in naturally occurring events. In simulations,

however, they can be provided singly or jointly and, if the latter, they can be made consistent or

be put in competition. Listeners were to indicate, by pressing a key, when the simulated siren

passed right in front of them. Each type of change on its own was sufficient to support perception

of the moment of pass-by but listeners were most accurate when all three types of change were

available and consistent. When placed in competition, that is, when the three variables simulated

different times of passage, listeners were biased in favor of amplitude change. Doppler shift

fared least well in competition, perhaps because this variable is least generalit is not detectable

for sounds that lack pitch change (clicks, squeaks, and slow velocities).

Unlike the rectilinear approaches, the transverse events included the moment of pass-by.

The importance of this structure has been assessed directly (Rosenblum, Wuestefeld, & Saldaa,

1993). Recordings of an approaching car at two speeds, 15 mph and 25 mph, were divided into

thirds and combinations of these thirds were presented to six listeners who were provided with

practice trials but no feedback. Judgments of time to arrival were as accurate when the acoustic

signal contained the actual time of passage as when it did not, showing the importance of
Ecological acoustics

36

acoustic structure before the moment of arrival. However, systematic occlusion or removal of

portions of the acoustic signal interferes with listeners ability to judge time to arrival

(Rosenblum, 1993). Thus, if the time-varying aspect of the acoustic signal provides information

about time to arrival, performance declines as this information is degraded or impoverished

(Wuestefled & Rosenblum, 1996).

A direct evaluation of one of the derived quantities, the intensity-based for pass-by,

found mixed results (Erwin, 1995). Simulated pass-by events used intensity modulated sine

waves (1000 Hz) to vary speed while keeping offset distance from the listener constant, or to

vary offset distance while keeping speed constant. Events were truncated before the object

passed in front of the listener who pressed a key to indicate when that pass-by would have

occurred. The constant error of those judgments varied as a function of the moment of inflection

of the -functions but with opposite signs for the two manipulations.

What do these results tell us about the information for imminent contact? In many

treatments of similar phenomena, each of the acoustic variables and portions of the signal might

be labeled a source of information (e.g., Cutting, 1986) and the event would be said to be

multiply specified. To our way of thinking, however, there is only one source and that is the

moving, sound-emitting object. Amplitude changes, Doppler shift and interaural differences are

simply variables that accompany that event. They probably combine in a non-linear fashion to

form a higher order variable (cf. Michaels & Carello, 1981) specific to time to arrival.

Controlling collisions is actually a rather general phenomenon (Kugler, Turvey, Carello, &

Shaw, 1985). An obvious example includes braking before crashing. Less obvious examples

include muscle activation preparatory to landing after jumping from a height (Sidaway, McNitt-

Gray, & Davis, 1989) or making postural adjustments to stay with the region of reversibility for
Ecological acoustics

37

balance (Carello, Turvey, & Kugler, 1985; Riccio, 1993). Guiding the filling of a vessel to the

brim with liquid also qualifies as a controlled collision and this one has been examined

acoustically (Cabe & Pittenger, 2000). For a closed cylindrical tube, the fundamental resonant

frequency is influenced by the height of the air column in the tube, the radius of the tube, and

the speed of sound in air. As the tube is filled, the column of air shortens and increases but as

the tube is drained, the column of air lengthens and decreases. If liquid is released at the same

rate it is introduced, should not change. Acoustic structure, therefore, distinguishes these three

events. Monophonic tape recordings of 3 filling events, 3 emptying events, and 3 maintenance

events were created with water flowing from a spigot into a plastic tube (30 cm long with a

radius of 5 cm). Randomized blocks of the nine events were presented nine times to nine

listeners over a loudspeaker without practice or feedback. Given three possible events, chance

performance was 33%. Listeners exceeded this in all cases: 67% correct for filling, 87% for

emptying, and 67% for maintaining.

Subsequent experiments had more of the flavor of visual experiments in that the listeners

actively controlled the flow of water through the spigot and arrested the stream to effect one of

two outcomes: full to the brim or to preferred drinking level. Their level of accuracy was

established with full informationholding a 17.5 cm long tube while watching and hearing it

fill. For audition alone, their eyes were closed and they did not hold the tube. Ten listeners in

each information condition were instructed to turn the water on and off only once during each of

30 trials. The tubes were filled to 96% capacity under full information and to 88% for auditory

information alone. For preferred drinking level, they were filled to 86% and 70%, respectively.

Although the particular levels achieved under auditory control differed from the particular levels

achieved under full information control, auditory control nonetheless allowed listeners to
Ecological acoustics

38

distinguish the two levels of fullness.

More variation in the acoustic signal was introduced by the use of three different vessel

volumes and two different flow rates (with 10 trials of each combination). Ten blindfolded

listeners were instructed to fill each vessel to the brim with one opening and closing of the

spigot. They were not told of the variations in vessel size or flow rate. Although there was a

tendency to underfill vessels (at the fast rate, small vessels were filled to 95% capacity, medium

to 86%, and large to 77%; at the fast rate, small vessels were filled to 94% capacity, medium to

85%, and large to 74%), generally the larger the vessel, the higher the fill level. Moreover, ten

blind listeners who performed the same task produced the same pattern of results. Finally, a

counterpart to the truncated approach and pass-by events described earlier (i.e., indicate when the

object would have hit you had it continued) required listeners to anticipate the end point of the

filling event in the absence of continuing acoustic structure. Nine listeners heard filling events

controlled by the Experimenter. Three flow rates were used to fill one vessel to 1/4, 1/2, or 3/4

full. Once the spigot was closed, listeners waited to respond until they thought the vessel would

have been full had that flow rate continued. Estimated time to fill tracked actual time to fill very

well (with 80-90% of the variance being accounted for).

The problem of synthesis

The Warren and Verbrugge (1984) study provides a model for doing ecological acoustics

research: Establish the ability, identify candidate sound variables, and produce synthetic events

on this basis. The process of synthesis is a tricky one, however. It can be motivated by the

structure of natural events or it can be motivated by the idealized structure expected from the

physical equations for the events. One problem with the latter is that the events are simple and
Ecological acoustics

39

idealized, with putatively messy structure eliminated, quite likely at the cost of informativeness.

Our survey of experimental investigations of auditory source perception strongly suggests that

listeners are good when they have a lot of acoustical structure, even if that acoustical structure is

not readily quantified by the scientists. In contrast, it seems to be the case that when events are

constrained so that the scientist has a better understanding of the sound structure, perceiving the

source becomes harder for the listener.

The issues are readily illustrated by the methods and arguments presented in an

investigation of auditory discrimination of the material composition of struck, clamped bars

(Lutfi & Oh, 1997). The sounds were synthesized according to principles of theoretical acoustics,

with material composition as the only difference between bars. Each material was uniquely

identified by nominal values of frequency, amplitude, and decay (which were chosen to be in a

range that typically allowed discrimination performance in the range of 70-85% correct). The

sounds were presented over headphones in a sound attenuation chamber. Their six listeners were

musically trained, with extensive practice and feedback in each condition (e.g., they were told

that the sounds would differ in pitch, loudness, and decay). The task was a 2 AFC: which tone

was the iron bar (where the alternatives were silver, steel, or copper) or which tone was he glass

bar (where the alternatives were crystal, quartz, or aluminum). There were 4000 trials per listener

for the iron bar as target and 4000 trials per listener with the glass bar as target. The basic result

was that all listeners depended excessively on frequency, with a reduction in performance

efficiency that sometimes approached 80%.

The investigators characterized their setting as a best case scenario (p. 3647)they had

made the task for the listener as straightforward as possibleyet performance was less than

ideal. Consequently, they suggested that the optimistic view that sources are perceived on the
Ecological acoustics

40

basis of available information (Gibson, 1966/1983; Fowler, 1990) was not supported because

listeners did not optimize decisions based on appropriate combinations of frequency, amplitude,

and decay (p. 3655). Instead, listeners seemed to make inferences based on only a single cue

(cf. Wildes & Richards, 1988). While acknowledging the constraints on their experimental

setting, these investigators thought that inexperienced listeners and multiply varying sound

sources ought to make the task even harder. As already discussed, this expectation is belied by

recent findings: Listeners exposed to actual impact events that included variation of shape were

nearly perfect in the identification of material (Kunkler-Peck & Turvey, 2000). Far from causing

listeners difficulties, the added natural variation seems to have made the relevant time-varying

structure more readily apparent.

Synthesizing events is not an inherently bad thing for ecologically oriented psychologists.

The issue is simply one of what is being synthesized. Gibson himself put the issue in terms of

synthesizing information (see also Gaver, 1993b). Work on dynamic touch (that based in the

states of muscles and tendons) provides a model. The description of an object with respect to its

inertia tensor is a description that is relevant to the role of touch in controlling movements. This

particular role can be understood as the proper function (cf. Millikan, 1984, 1993) of dynamic

touch. This is the function that dynamic touch has served throughout evolution that has

encouraged its survival. Dynamic touch is not so much a property-analyzing system as it is a

system for controlling movements of limbs and hand-held objects. When scientists manipulate

the inertial characteristics of an experimental object, they are synthesizing information about its

movableness not about it mass or length or diameter.

The parallel for audition seems more likely to be found in sound effects on old-time radio

(e.g., alternately slapping coconut halves to simulate a galloping horse), which are really more in
Ecological acoustics

41

the spirit of synthesizing information than the technically more sophisticated simulations

permitted by theoretical acoustics. The success of auditory metaphors in cinema, exploited in the

musical scoring that accompanies lurking madmen or sea battles or madcap exploits, points to

the abstractness of the information that is unlikely to be found in nominal values of physical

parameters of frequency, amplitude, and decay.


Ecological acoustics

42

References

Anderson, K., Carello, C., & Kunkler-Peck, A. J. (May, 1996). Rotational inertia constrains

perception of object length by sound. Poster presented at the North American Society for

Ecological Psychology. Hartford, CT.

Bingham, G. P. (1993). Perceiving the size of trees: Forms as information about scale. Journal of
Experimental Psychology: Human Perception & Performance, 19, 1139-1161.

Bingham, G. P., Rosenblum, L. D., & Schmidt, R. C. (1995). Dynamics and the orientation of

kinematic forms in visual event recognition. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human


Perception and Performance, 21, 1473-1493.

Bootsma, R. J., & Oudejans, R. R. D. (1993). Visual information about time-to-collision between

two objects. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 19,

1041-1052.

Cabe, P., & Pittenger, J. B. (2000). Human sensitivity to acoustic information from vessel filling.

Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 26, 313-324.

Carello, C., Anderson, K. L., & Peck, A. (1998). Perception of object length by sound.

Psychological Science, 9, 211-214.

Carello, C., Grosofsky, A., Reichel, F. D., Solomon, H. Y., & Turvey, M. T. (1989). Visually

perceiving what is reachable. Ecological Psychology, 1, 27-54.


Carello, C., Turvey, M. T., & Kugler, P.N. (1985). The informational support for upright stance.

Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 8, 151-152.

Chomsky, C. (1986). Analytic study of the Tadoma method: Language abilities of three deaf-

blind subjects. Journal of Speech and Hearing Research, 29, 332-347.

Clifton, R., Perris, E., & Bullinger, A. (1991). Infants perception of auditory space.

Developmental Psychology, 27, 187-197.

Cutting, J. E. (1986). Perception with an eye for motion. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Diehl, R., & Walsh, M. (1989). An auditory basis for the stimulus-length effect in the perception
Ecological acoustics

43

of stops and glides. Journal of the Acoustical Society of America, 85, 2154-2164.

Erwin, T. (1995). Prospective acoustic information for object pass by. In B. G. Bardy, R. J.

Bootsma, & Y. Guiard (Eds.), Studies in perception and action III (pp. 325-328). Mahwah,

NJ: Erlbaum.

Fitzpatrick, P., Carello, C., Schmidt, R. C., & Corey, D. (1994). Haptic and visual perception of

an affordance for upright posture. Ecological Psychology, 6, 265-287.

Fitzpatrick, P., Carello, C., & Turvey, M. T. (1994). Eigenvalues of the inertia tensor and

exteroception by the muscular sense. Neuroscience, 60, 551-568.


Fletcher, N. H., & Rossing, T. D. (1991). The physics of musical instruments. New York:

Springer-Verlag.

Fowler, C. A. (1986). An event approach to the study of speech perception from a direct-realist

perspective. Journal of Phonetics, 14, 3-28.

Fowler, C. A. (1990). Sound-producing sources as object of perception: Rate normalization and

nonspeech perception. Journal of the Acoustical Society of America, 88, 1236-1249.

Fowler, C. A. (1991). Auditory perception is not special: We see the world, we feel the world,

we hear the world. Journal of the Acoustical Society of America, 89, 2910-2915.

Fowler, C. A., & Dekle, D. J. (1991). Listening with eye and hand: Cross-modal contributions to

speech production. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and


Performance, 17, 816-828.

Freed, D. J. (1990). Auditory correlates of perceived mallet hardness for a set of recorded

percussive events. Journal of the Acoustical Society of America, 87, 311-322.

Friberg, A., & Sundberg, J. (1999). Does music performance allude to locomotion? A model of

final ritardandi derived from measurements of stopping runners. Journal of the Acoustical

Society of America, 105, 1469-1484.

Gaver, W. W. (1988). Everyday listening and auditory icons. Unpublished doctoral dissertation,

University of California, San Diego.


Ecological acoustics

44

Gaver, W. W. (1993a). What in the world do we hear? An ecological approach to auditory event

perception. Ecological Psychology, 5, 1-29.

Gaver, W. W. (1993b). How do we hear in the world? Explorations in ecological acoustics.

Ecological Psychology, 5, 285-313.

Gibson, E. J. (1994). Has psychology a future? Psychological Science, 5, 69-76.

Gibson, J. J. (1983). The senses considered as perceptual systems. Prospect Heights, IL:

Wavelan. (Original work published in 1966)

Gibson, J. J. (1979). The ecological approach to visual perception. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.
Gordon, C., & Webb, D. (1996). You cant hear the shape of a drum. American Scientist, 84, 46-

55.

GrandPr, D., & Carello, C. (2001). Elasticity and length perception by dynamic touch. In G.

Burton & R. C. Schmidt (Eds.), Studies in perception and action, VI (pp. 21-24). Mahwah,

NJ: Erlbaum.

Guski, R. (1992). Acoustic tau: an easy analog to visual tau? Ecological Psychology, 4, 189-197.

Heft, H. (1993). A methodological note on overestimates of reaching distance: Distinguishing

between perceptual and analytic judgments. Ecological Psychology, 5, 255-271.

Jenkins, J. J. (1985). Acoustic information for places, objects, and events. In W. H. Warren & R.

E. Shaw (Eds.), Persistence and change: Proceedings of the first international conference on
event perception (pp. 115-138). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.

Johansson, G. (1973). Visual perception of biological motion and a model for its analysis.

Perception & Psychophysics, 14, 201-211

Kac, M. (1966). Can one hear the shape of a drum? Mathematics Monthly, 13, 21-23.

Keller, H. (1903). The story of my life. New York: Doubleday.

Kugler, P.N., Turvey, M. T., Carello, C., & Shaw, R. E. (1985). The physics of controlled

collisions: A reverie about locomotion. In W. H. Warren & R. E. Shaw (Eds.), Persistence

and Change: Proceedings of the First International Conference on Event Perception (pp.
Ecological acoustics

45

195-222). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.

Kunkler-Peck, A., & Turvey, M. T. (2000). Hearing shape. Journal of Experimental Psychology:

Human Perception and Performance, 1, 279-294.

Lakatos, S., McAdams, S., & Causs, R. (1997). The representation of auditory source

characteristics: Simple geometric form. Perception & Psychophysics, 59, 1180-1190.

Lee, D. N. (1976). A theory of visual control of braking based on information about time-to-

collision. Perception, 5, 437-459.


Lee, D. N. (1980). Visuo-motor coordination in space-time. In G. Stelmach, & J. Requin (Eds.),

Tutorials in motor behavior (pp. 281-295). Amsterdam: North Holland Press.

Lee, D. N. (1990). Getting around with light or sound. In R. Warren & A. Wertheim, (eds.).

Perception and control of self-motion (pp. 487-505). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.

Li, X., Logan, R. J., & Pastore, R. E. (1991). Perception of acoustic source characteristics:

Walking sounds. Journal of the Acoustical Society of America, 90, 3036-3049.

Liberman, A. M. (1982). On finding that speech is special. American Psychologist, 37, 148-167.

Liberman, A. M., Cooper, F., Shankweiler, D., & Studdert-Kennedy, M. (1967). Perception of

the speech code. Psychological Review, 74, 431-461.

Liberman, A. M., Ingemann, F., Lisker, L., Delattre, P., & Cooper, F. (1959). Minimal rules for

synthesizing speech. Journal of the Acoustical Society of America, 31, 1490-1499.


Liberman, A. M., & Mattingly, I. (1985). The motor theory revised. Cognition, 21, 1-36.

Liberman, A. M., & Mattingly, I. (1989). A specialization for speech perception. Science, 243,

489-494.

Lichte, W. H. (1941). Attributes of complex tones. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 28, 455-

480.

Lutfi, R. A., & Oh, E. (1997). Auditory discrimination of material changes in a struck-clamped

bar. Journal of the Acoustical Society of America, 102, 3647-3656.

MacDonald, J. W., & McGurk, H. (1978). Visual influences on speech perception processes.
Ecological acoustics

46

Perception & Psychophysics, 24, 253-257.

McGurk, H. & MacDonald, J. W. (1976). Hearing lips and seeing voices. Nature, 264, 746-748.

Massaro, D. (1987). Speech perception by ear and eye: A paradigm for psychological inquiry.

Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.

Massaro, D. (1998). Perceiving talking faces. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Michaels, C. F. (1986). An ecological analysis of binocular vision. Psychological Research, 48,

1-22.

Michaels, C. F., & Carello, C. (1981). Direct perception. New York: Prentice Hall.
Michaels, C. F., Prindle, S., & Turvey, M. T. (1985). A note on the natural basis of action

categories: The catching distance of mantids. Journal of Motor Behavior, 17, 255-264.

Miller, J., & Liberman, A. M. (1979). Some effects of later-occurring information on the

perception of stop consonant and semivowel. Perception & Psychophysics, 25, 457-465.

Millikan, R. (1984). Language, thought and other biological categories. Cambridge, MA: MIT

Press.

Millikan, R. (1993). White queen psychology and other essays for Alice. Cambridge, MA: MIT

Press.

Norman, J. F., Todd, J. T., Perotti, V. J., & Tittle, J. S., (1996). The visual perception of three-

dimensional length. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception &


Performance, 22, 173-186.

Perris, E., & Clifton, R. K. (1988). Reaching in the dark toward sound as a measure of auditory

localization in infants. Infant Behavior and Development,11, 473-491.

Prinz, W. (1997). Perception-action planning. European Journal of Cognitive Psychology, 9,

129-154.

Repp, B. H. (1987). The sound of two hands clapping: An exploratory study. Journal of the

Acoustical Society of America, 81, 1100-1110.

Riccio, G. E. (1993). Information in movement variability about the qualitative dynamics of


Ecological acoustics

47

posture and orientation. In K. M. Newell & D. M. Corcos (Eds.) Variability and motor

control (pp. 317-358). Champaign, IL: Human Kinetics.

Rosenblum, L. D. (1993). Acoustical information for controlled collisions. In A. Schick (Ed.),

Contributions to psychological acoustics (pp. 303-322). Oldenberg, Germany: Bibliotheks.

Rosenblum, L. D., & Saldaa, H. (1996). An audiovisual test of kinematic primitives for visual

speech perception. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and

Performance, 22, 318-331.


Rosenblum, L. D., & Saldaa, H. (1998). Time-varying information for visual speech perception.

In R. Campell, B. Dodd, & D. Burnham (Eds.). Hearing by eye II: Advances in the

psychology of speech reading and auditory-visual speech (pp. 61-81). Hillsdale, NJ:

Erlbaum.

Rosenblum, L. D., Carello, C., & Pastore, R. E. (1987). Relative effectiveness of three stimulus

variables for locating a moving sound source. Perception, 16, 175-186.

Rosenblum, L. D., Johnson, J., & Saldaa, H. (1996). Point-light facial displays enhance

comprehension of speech in noise. Journal of Speech and Hearing Research, 29, 1159-1170.

Rosenblum, L. D., Wuestefeld, A., & Anderson, K. (1996). Auditory reachability: an affordance

approach to the perception of distance. Ecological Psychology, 8, 1-24.

Rosenblum, L. D., Wuestefeld, A., & Saldaa, H. (1993). Auditory looming perception:

influences on anticipator judgments. Perception, 22, 1467-1482.


Rossing, T. D., & Fletcher, N. H. (1995). Principles of vibrations and sound. New York:

Springer-Verlag.

Russell, M. & Turvey, M. T. (1999). Auditory perception of unimpeded passage. Ecological

Psychology, 11, 175-188.

Schiff, W., & Oldak, R. (1990). Accuracy of judging time to arrival: Effects of modality,

trajectory, and gender. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and

Performance, 16, 303-316.


Ecological acoustics

48

Schubert, E. D. (1975). The role of auditory perception in language processing. In M. Rawson &

D. D. Duane (Eds.), Language, perception and reading (pp. 97-130). Baltimore, MD: York.

Shaw, B. K., McGowan, R., & Turvey, M. T. (1991). An acoustic variable specifying time to

contact. Ecological Psychology, 3, 253-261.

Shockley, K., Grocki, M., Carello, C., & Turvey, M. T. (in press). Heaviness perception

implicates an ecological form of the rigid body laws. Experimental Brain Research.

Sidaway, B., McNitt-Gray, J., & Davis, G. (1989). Visual timing of muscle preactivation in

preparation for landing. Ecological Psychology, 1, 253-264.


Snyder, W. S., Cook, M. J., Nasset, E. S., Karhausen, L. R., Howells, G. P., & Tipton, I. H.

(1974). Report of the task group on reference man. Oxford, England: Pergamon

Stoffregen, T. A., & Pittenger, J. B. (1995). Human echolocation as a basic form of perception

and action. Ecological Psychology, 7, 181-216.

Studdert-Kennedy, M. (1985). Perceiving phonetic events. In R. Shaw & W. H. Warren (Eds.),

Persistence and change: Proceedings of the first international conference on event

perception (pp. 139-156). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.

Sumby, W. H, & Pollack, I. (1954). Visual contribution to speech intelligibility in noise. Journal

of the Acoustical Society of America, 26, 212-215.

Summerfield, A. Q. (1987). Some preliminaries to a comprehensive account of audiovisual

speech perception. In B. Dodd & R. Campbell (Eds.), Hearing by eye: The psychology of
lip-reading (pp. 3-51). London: Erlbaum.

Todd, J. T. (1981). Visual information about moving objects. Journal of Experimental

Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 7, 795-810.

Tousman, S. A., & Pastore, R. E. (1989). Source characteristics: A study of hand clapping.

Journal of the Acoustical Society of America Supplement 1, 85, S53.

Tresilian, J. R. (1993). Four questions of time to contact: A critical examination of research on

interceptive timing. Perception, 22, 653-680.


Ecological acoustics

49

Turvey, M. T. (1992). Affordances and prospective control: An outline of the ontology.

Ecological Psychology, 4, 173-187.

Turvey, M. T. (1996). Dynamic touch. American Psychologist, 51, 1134-1152.

Turvey, M. T., & Carello, C. (1995). Dynamic touch. In W. Epstein & S. Rogers (Eds.),

Handbook of perception and cognition, Vol. 5. Perception of space and motion (pp. 401-

490). New York: Academic Press.

Turvey, M. T., Shockley, K., & Carello, C. (1999). Affordance, proper function, and the physical

basis of perceived heaviness. Cognition, 17, B17-B26.


Venderveer, N. J. (1979). Ecological acoustics: Human perception of environmental sounds.

Dissertation Abstracts International. 40/09B, 4543. (University Microfilms No. 8004002).

Warren, W. H., & Verbrugge, R. R. (1984). Auditory perception of breaking and bouncing

events: A case study in ecological acoustics. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human

Perception and Performance, 10, 704-712.

Warren, W. H., & Whang, S. (1987). Visual guidance of walking through apertures: Body-scaled

information for affordances. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and

Performance, 13, 371-383.

Wightman, F. L., & Jenison, R. (1995). Auditory spatial layout. In W. Epstein & S. J. Rogers

(Eds.) Perception of space and motion (pp. 365-400). San Diego: Academic Press.
Wildes, R., & Richards, W. (1988). Recovering material properties from sound. In W. Richards

(Ed.), Natural computation (pp. 356-363). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Wuestefeld, A., & Rosenblum, L. (1996). Perceptual learning in an auditory time to arrival task.

Technical Report UCR.96.011. University of California, Riverside.


Ecological acoustics

50

Authors Notes

Preparation of this manuscript was supported by grants from the National Science Foundation

(SBR 97-09678 awarded to M. T. Turvey and Claudia Carello) and the National Institutes of

Health (HD 01994) awarded to Haskins Laboratories.

You might also like