0% found this document useful (0 votes)
51 views

MATH 229: Theory of Functions of Real Variables: 1 Preliminaries

This document provides an overview of preliminary concepts for a course on theory of functions of real variables. It defines algebras and σ-algebras of sets, and discusses their properties including closure under unions and intersections. Functions, sequences, and mappings between sets are introduced. Finite and countable sets are defined, and it is shown that subsets of countable sets are also countable, as are sets of finite sequences from a countable set. The rational numbers are proven to be countable, and the union of countably many countable sets is countable.
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
51 views

MATH 229: Theory of Functions of Real Variables: 1 Preliminaries

This document provides an overview of preliminary concepts for a course on theory of functions of real variables. It defines algebras and σ-algebras of sets, and discusses their properties including closure under unions and intersections. Functions, sequences, and mappings between sets are introduced. Finite and countable sets are defined, and it is shown that subsets of countable sets are also countable, as are sets of finite sequences from a countable set. The rational numbers are proven to be countable, and the union of countably many countable sets is countable.
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 4

MATH 229: Theory of Functions of Real Variables

Lawrence A. Eclarin, Ph.D.


Mariano Marcos State University

1 Preliminaries
1.1 Algebra of Sets
Definition 1.1. A collection A of subsets of a set X is called an algebra of sets or a
Boolean algebra if

i. A ∪ B ∈ A whenever A, B ∈ A , and

ii. ∼ A ∈ A whenever A ∈ A .

Remark. By De Morgan’s Law, A ∩ B ∈ A whenever A, B ∈ X. That is, suppose A


and B are in A then ∼ A, ∼ B ∈ A and (∼ A) ∪ (∼ B) =∼ (A ∩ B) ∈ A . Hence, A ∩ B
is in A .

1. If A is an algebra on X, then X and ∅ are in A .

Proof. Suppose that A ∈ A , then ∼ A is in A . Thus, A ∪ (∼ A) = X ∈ A .


Moreover, ∼ X = ∅. Hence, it is also in A .

2. An algebra is closed under finite unions.

Proof. Let A1 , A2 , . . . , An be sets in A . Then

A1 ∪ A2 ∈ A
(A1 ∪ A2 ) ∪ A3 ∈ A
..
.
(A1 ∪ A2 . . . ∪ An−1 ) ∪ An ∈ A .

3. An algebra is closed under finite intersections.

Proof. Exercise

Examples:

1. A = {∅, X} is an algebra.

1
Theory of Functions of Real Variables Eclarin, L. A.

2. The powerset of X, P(X), is an algebra.

3. Let X = {a, b, c, d}.

(a) A = {∅, {a}, {b, c, d}, X} is an algebra.


(b) B = {∅, {a}, {a, b}, {b, c, d}, {c, d}, X} is not an algebra.

Proposition 1.1. Given any collection C of subsets of X, there is a smallest algebra A


which contains C ; that is, there is an algebra A containing C and such that if B is any
algebra containing C , then B contains A .
Proof. First, we let F be the family of all algebras that contain C (i.e., if B is an algebra
containing C , then
\ B ∈ F ).
Define A = B. Then C ⊆ A since each B ∈ F contains C .
B∈F
Now, we show that A is an algebra.
Suppose A, B ∈ A , then A, B ∈ B for each B in F , by definition. Thus, A\
∪B ∈ B
since B is an algebra. Note that this is true for all B ∈ F . Hence, A ∪ B ∈ B.
B∈F
Similarly, if A ∈ A then A ∈ B for each B in F and ∼ A ∈ B since B is an algebra.
Thus, ∼ A ∈ A .
Therefore, if B is an algebra containing C , then B is contains A .

Proposition 1.2. Let A be an algebra of subsets and hAi i a sequence of sets in A . Then
there is a sequence hBi i of sets in A such that Bn ∩ Bm = ∅ for n 6= m and

[ ∞
[
Bi = Ai .
i=1 i=1

Proof. If we assume that hAi i is finite, then the conclusion follows.


Suppose hAi i is an infinite sequence. Let B1 = A1 and let

Bn = An ∼ [A1 ∪ A2 ∪ . . . ∪ An−1 ]
= An ∩ (∼ A1 ) ∩ (∼ A2 ) ∩ . . . ∩ (∼ An−1 ) for n ∈ N.

Then, Bn ∈ A for each n. Moreover, Bn ⊂ An .


Consider Bn and Bm and suppose that m < n. Then

Bm ∩ Bn ⊂ Am ∩ An ∩ . . . ∩ (∼ Am ) ∩ . . . ∩ (∼ An−1 )
= Am ∩ (∼ Am ) ∩ An ∩ . . . ∩ (∼ An−1 )
= ∅ ∩ An ∩ . . . ∩ (∼ An−1 )
= ∅

Since Bi ⊂ Ai for all i, then



[ ∞
[
Bi ⊂ Ai .
i=1 i=1

1 PRELIMINARIES 2
Theory of Functions of Real Variables Eclarin, L. A.

Let x ∈ ∞
S
Sx∞∈ Ai for some i. Let n be the smallest i such that this is so.
i=1 Ai . Then
Then x ∈ Bn and so x ∈ i=1 Bi . Hence

[ ∞
[
Ai ⊂ Bi .
i=1 i=1

Definition 1.2. An algebra A of sets is called a σ-algebra, or a Borel field, if every


union of a countable collection of sets in A is again in A .
Remark. By De Morgan’s laws, it follows that the intersection of a countable collection
of sets in A is again in A .
Proposition 1.3. Given any collection C of subsets of X, there is a smallest σ-algebra
that contains C ; that is, there is a σ-algebra A containing C such that if B is any
σ-algebra containing C , then A ⊂ B.
The smallest σ-algebra containing C is called the σ-algebra generated by C .

1.2 Finite and Countable Sets


Definition 1.3. Consider two sets X and Y and suppose that with each element x of
X there is associated an element of Y , which we denote by f (x). Then f is said to be
a function or mapping from X to Y . The set X is called the domain of f , and the
elements f (x) in Y are called the values of f . The set of all values of f is called the
range of f .
Remark. We express the fact that f is a function of X into Y by writing

f : X → Y.

The range of f is generally smaller than Y . If the range of f is Y , then we say that f is
a function onto Y (or f is surjective).
Definition 1.4. Let X and Y be two sets and let f : X → Y . If A ⊂ X, the image
under f of A is defined as the set of elements y in Y such that y = f (x) for some x ∈ A.
This image is denoted by f [A]. That is,

f [A] = {y ∈ Y | (∃x) [x ∈ A and y = f (x)]}.

Remark. With this notation, the range of f is f [X], and f is onto Y if and only if
Y = f [X].
Definition 1.5. Let f : X → Y and suppose that B ⊂ Y . The inverse image of B
under f is the set
f −1 [B] = {x ∈ X| f (x) ∈ B}.
Remark. If for every y ∈ Y , f −1 (y) consists of at most one element of X, then f is said
to be a one-to-one mapping of X into B.
Definition 1.6. If there exists a one-to-one mapping of X onto Y , then the function
f : X → Y is a one-to-one correspondence.

1 PRELIMINARIES 3
Theory of Functions of Real Variables Eclarin, L. A.

Remark. If there is a one-to-one correspondence between the sets X and Y , then X


and Y have the same cardinal number, or, that X and Y are equivalent, and we write
X ≡ Y . This relation has the following properties:

1. It is reflexive: X ≡ X.

2. It is symmetric: If X ≡ Y , then Y ≡ X.

3. It is transitive: If X ≡ Y and Y ≡ Z, then X ≡ Z.

Hence, ≡ is an equivalence relation.

For finite sets, it is evident that X ≡ Y if and only if the two sets have the same
number of elements. Thus, a finite set cannot be equivalent to one of its proper subsets.
For infinite sets, the cardinality or number of elements in the sets is not a specific
number but are equal for equivalent sets. Moreover, an infinite set may be equivalent to
one of its proper subset.

Definition 1.7. A sequence is a function defined on the set N of all natural numbers.
If f (n) = xn , for n ∈ N, the sequence is denoted as {xn } = x1 , x2 , . . . where the xi ’s are
called the terms of the sequence.

Definition 1.8. A set is called finite if it is either empty or the range of a finite sequence.
A set is called countable if it is either empty or the range of a sequence.

Remarks.

1. The image of a countable set is countable, i.e., the range of any function with a
countable domain is itself countable, and similarly for finite sets.

2. Any set that can be put in one-to-one correspondence with a finite set is finite
and any set that can be put in one-to-one correspondence with a countable set is
countable.

3. Any set which can be put in one-to-one correspondence with the set N of natural
numbers is countably infinite.

4. If an infinite set E is the range of a sequence hxn i, then E can be put in one-to-one
correspondence with N.

Proposition 1.4. Every subset of a countable set is countable.

Proposition 1.5. Let A be a countable set. Then the set of all finite sequences from A
is also countable.

Proposition 1.6. The set of all rational numbers is countable.

Proposition 1.7. The union of a countable collection of countable sets is countable.

1 PRELIMINARIES 4

You might also like