4E Cognition
4E Cognition
4E Cognition
The debate about the role of the body in cognition has been ongoing since close
to the beginnings of philosophy. In Plato’s dialogue The Phaedo, for example,
Socrates considers the idea, which he attributes to Anaxagoras, that one could
explain his decision to remain in prison by a purely material or physical
explanation in terms of bodily mechanisms. Socrates himself rejects this idea—
surely, he thinks, there is something more to reason than just bodily processes.
Aristotle, however, was motivated by the idea that Anaxagoras was not entirely
wrong. While Aristotle did not accept the radical view of Anaxagoras, he
considered that the body (with special reference to the hands) may play some
role in what makes for human rationality. Such debates considering the role of
the body for the mind can be traced through medieval texts authored by
Neoplatonists, Aquinas, and others, and are given their modern formulations in
thinkers such as Spinoza, La Mettrie, Condillac, and many others. Pragmatists,
phenomenologists, and philosophers of mind wrestle with the same issues
throughout the twentieth century. The more proximate background for the
current debates about embodied cognition, however, is to be found in the
disagreements between behaviorists and cognitivists. Continuing tensions within
cognitivism, and the cognitive sciences more generally, brought on by
contrasting functionalist and neurobiological accounts that tended to ignore the
role of body and environment and focus on internalist explanations of brain
function, set the stage for the emergence of contemporary views on embodied
cognition.
In the 1990s, Varela, Thompson, and Rosch’s (1991) The Embodied Mind,
drawing on phenomenological and neurobiological resources, proposed an
enactivist account of cognition that emphasized the role of the dynamical
coupling of brain–body– environment. Around the same time, a paper by Flor
und Hutchins (1991) introduced distributed cognition as a “new branch of
cognitive science” for which the unit of analysis includes external structures,
collectives, and artifacts organized as a system to perform a task. Hutchins’s
(1995) Cognition in the Wild was a direct influence on Clark and Chalmers’s
(1998) now-classic philosophical essay, “The Extended Mind.” Throughout this
time period, additional work inspired by Gibson’s ecological approach to
psychology contributed to a growing realization that cognition was not limited to
processes in the head, but was embodied, embedded, extended, and enactive.
KEY CONCEPTS
Before introducing the key concepts in the debate, we first need to consider
whether there are certain constraints that need to be taken into account in order
to answer the question of what cognition is and how we should individuate
cognitive processes.
During the past couple of decades, these key elements of the RCC—the pivotal
role of computation and representation in all cognitive processing and the pivotal
role of a central processing unit in the brain as the sole relevant factor of
cognitive processing—have come under pressure (Gallagher 2005; Walter
2014). Proponents of 4E cognition have argued against the assumption that
cognition is an isolated and abstract, quasi-Cartesian affair in a central
processing unit in a brain. This idea is typically associated with functionalism,
which claims that cognitive phenomena are fully determined by their functional
role and therefore form an autonomous level of analysis. According to
proponents of 4E cognition, however, the cognitive phenomena that are studied
by modern cognitive science, such as spatial navigation, action, perception, and
understanding other’s emotions, are in some sense all dependent on the
morphological, biological, and physiological details of an agent’s body, an
appropriately structured natural, technological, or social environment, and the
agent’s active and embodied interaction with this environment. Even most of the
phenomena studied by traditional cognitive science—such as language
processing (e.g., Glenberg and Kaschak 2002), memory (Casasanto and Dijkstra
2010), visual-motor recalibration (Bhalla and Proffitt 1999) and perception-
based distance estimation (Witt and Proffitt 2008)—are not abstract, modality-
unspecific processes in a central processing area either, but essentially rely on
the system’s body and its dynamical and reciprocal real-time interaction with its
environment.
a.
b.
c.
d.
The last version of the claim (d) is identical with the property of being
embedded, i.e., being causally dependent on extrabodily processes in the
environment of the bodily system. Furthermore, being extended is a property of
a cognitive process if it is at least partially constituted by extrabodily processes
(b), i.e., if it extends into essentially involved extrabodily components or tools
(Stephan et al. 2014; Walter 2014).
e.
f.
Mental Representations
Since the volume is organized in nine additional parts, we will provide a short
overview of the main questions that are treated in these parts.
The second part of essays explores the concept of cognition specifically from the
perspectives offered by 4E approaches to the mind. From a standard viewpoint,
the debates around embodied approaches seem to turn the “what” question into
the “where” question, so that the answer to the question about the nature of
cognition is first of all about location: precisely where is cognition located? In
this regard the line that demarcates between inside and outside plays an
important role. From the perspective of the 4Es, however, the question of
location is less critical; indeed, the distinction between inside and outside is
downplayed, and the boundary line turns out to be a movable and permeable
border. Thus, on the extended mind paradigm, if you happen to be using a piece
of the environment to assist memory or to solve a problem, then in that case the
mind extends into the environment; on the enactivist view, if there is a
dynamical coupling to others or to tools in joint action, then there is no line that
cuts the organism off from these other social and environmental factors.
Cognition is affordance-based, where affordances are always relational (between
the cognizing subject or some form of life and the possibilities offered by some
entity or complex of entities), and where entity may be some physical part of the
environment, another person who can provide information or opportunity, a
social or cultural structure, or even something more abstract, such as a concept
that, with some manipulation, offers a solution to a problem. Such approaches
transform the question about cognition into questions about the nature of
affordances, about whether cognition is extended or extensive, about what
precisely we mean by coupling, about whether a dynamical systems approach
can do without representations, and so forth.