Chapter 1 Origins
Chapter 1 Origins
Origins
Environmental problems
Nature is disappearing fast, or so we are led to believe. Fewer whales swim the
oceans. Fewer tigers stalk the Sundarbans of Bengal. Many coral reefs are bleaching,
and Borneo are threatened. Freak hurricanes blight the Caribbean and shred its trees.
Closer at hand, garden birds and butterflies are dwindling in number. In Britain, even
bluebells and Wordsworth’s wild daffodils are said to be endangered. What, we may
The natural world has long ceased to be a reliable backdrop to human life, unaffected
by human activity. For many centuries we have been changing it, through hunting and
farming, through building, mining, and engineering, and through travelling and
as the stars above us, but the environment that our grand-children inherit will be
vastly different from that of our early ancestors, and even from the environment we
were born into ourselves. We can no longer take it for granted, even if we ever could.
Because of human impacts on the world of nature, many people call the present age
‘the Anthropocene’, coining this term to echo geological ages such as the Eocene and
the Pleistocene. What they mean is that human impacts have become predominant
They fail to agree about when this age began. Did it begin with the invention of ships,
with the industrial revolution, or with the world wars of the twentieth century? There
is no agreement either on whether this means that it is too late to preserve the natural
world, whether we are free to re-mould the face of the Earth as we please (for a
version of this view, see the section of Chapter 6 on Social Ecology), or whether we
should use our knowledge and technology to restore tracts of the world to their pre-
human condition. But they agree that humankind has become one of the main
Deforestation and soil erosion are among ways in which people have changed the
natural world. Alongside positive developments such as the building of cities, others
include the loss of numerous species, the growth of deserts, the depletion of resources,
appeared inexhaustible. Problems only come to be recognized as such when they are
seen to involve avoidable harms, and when ways can be envisaged to solve or at least
alleviate them, as John Passmore has sagely remarked in Man’s Responsibility for
Nature.
Among philosophers, Plato (in his dialogue Critias) was one of the earliest to be
aware of soil erosion and deforestation, but he was untroubled by these developments,
as was his disciple Aristotle, who, in his Meteorologica, depicted nature as permanent
and fundamentally unchanging. It was not until the nineteenth century that people like
George Perkins Marsh, in Man and Nature (1864), came to regard nature as
3
significantly vulnerable to human activity, and at the same time human life as
The twentieth century saw the rise of ecological science, and the related study of
nature as composed of interacting natural systems, but the case for preserving systems
such as rivers and forests had to await the publication of Aldo Leopold’s A Sand
ecosystems, but philosophers and ethicists (Leopold was neither of these) remained
unimpressed. What may have served to change the atmosphere was Rachel Carson’s
work Silent Spring (1962), with its disclosure that pesticides such as DDT, used in
Another factor was the spectacle of defoliation used by American forces during the
biological warfare and to sequestrate or even eradicate the natural world of central
the environment, and how human action can imperil whole species and ecosystems,
here.]
Philosophical ethics had for some decades held back (at least in the Anglo-Saxon
world) from reflection on practical issues, focussing instead on the analysis and the
meaning of concepts. But from the 1960s new issues in medicine (such as
4
brought a new lease of life to the ancient sub-discipline of medical ethics, and the
The stage was thus set for the emergence in the early 1970s of environmental
concepts and problems. Up to the start of the twentieth century, philosophy had
philosophy of Plato, Aristotle, Spinoza, Locke, and Kant). The various branches of
applied philosophy now set about rescuing this longstanding tradition and bringing it
Sylvan), an Australian philosopher, gave an address entitled ‘Is There a Need for a
affirmative. He took the traditional Western view to be that only human interests
matter, and that we humans may treat nature as we please. He rejected this view on
For example, if ‘the Last Man’, a survivor of a nuclear holocaust, lays about him,
eliminating, as far as he can, every remaining living being, animal or vegetable, what
he does would be permissible for the traditional view, but in most people’s intuitive
environmental ethic at odds with the traditional view, and one which better responds
5
to the assaults of human beings on the natural world. We should thus reject the
extreme and exceptional circumstances that people’s intuitive judgements about them
cease to be reliable, let alone indicative of the principles that we need. Critics
suggested that, when judging the deeds of the Last Man, we inadvertently smuggle
back into the scenario assumptions that fit more normal cases. We assume (they say)
that other people or future people will somehow suffer from his behaviour, even
Yet Routley could reply that he needs to supply a scenario of this kind to allow us to
make judgements about a case where there are no remaining human interests (the Last
Man, we may imagine, is shortly going to die himself), and where the only interests at
stake are those of nonhuman animals and plants. Besides, he could insist that even in
cases where it is clear that no human interests remain at stake, most people still
environmental ethic was widely found to be persuasive. At the very least it seemed to
show that nonhuman animals should be taken into consideration in human decision-
presence of animal interests (if, say, all animals in the vicinity had been killed by the
same nuclear holocaust), the widespread judgement that the Last Man would be acting
6
wrongly in destroying, as far as he could, the surviving plants could be held to suggest
that the good of plants should be regarded as mattering, from an ethical perspective,
But was Routley right in his characterization of Western traditions? Routley was
Man’s Responsibility for Nature was published the following year (1974). Passmore
held that the majority view was human-centred and involved no ethical restrictions on
Yet he also recognized two minority traditions. In one of these, human beings are
stewards or trustees of the world of nature, and responsible for its care (hence the title
tradition, answerable for their stewardship to God. In the second tradition, the role of
human beings is to enhance or perfect the world of nature by co-operating with and
bringing out its potential. Both these ‘minority’ traditions were held to have ancient
roots and a long history in Western culture, and thus Passmore’s suggestion was that
these traditions, which are richer than is often recognized, but can rather involve
For his part, Routley maintained that Passmore’s ‘minority’ views were
into account non-human interests, need to be rejected and superseded. But these
claims can be contested; for there is evidence that both of Passmore’s ‘minority’
7
traditions were widely held and advocated in the early centuries of Christianity, and
are thus hardly minority traditions at all, and also that they can be interpreted (and
have long been interpreted) in ways that recognize the ethical importance of
nonhuman interests as well as the interests of human beings. (Much of this evidence
Routley’s contribution, then, was an important one with regard to the kind of ethic
required, but his narrow view of Western traditions and their resources needs to be
taken with a considerable pinch of salt. Many of the saints, for example, were
prominent in treating animals, both wild and domesticated, with concern and
In the same year as Routley’s World Congress address, the philosophical journal
philosopher Arne Naess, ‘The Shallow and the Deep, Long-Range Ecology
The shallow kind is concerned with human interests of the next fifty years or so, and
in particular with those of the people of developed countries. By contrast, the deep
kind is additionally concerned with the good of the people of developing countries,
with the long-term future, and with nonhuman species, affirming their ‘equal right to
live and blossom’. Naess recognized the practical need for some harvesting and
killing of animals and plants if human life was to continue, but still adhered in
8
Naess’s advocacy of the Deep Ecology movement involved support for a broad
probably having in mind its fostering of nonhuman life and enriching human life
simultaneously.
At the same time cultural diversity was commended too, together with opposition to
power of class. Pollution and resource-depletion were to be contested, not just local
forms affecting developed countries, or ones ignoring wider, global perspectives. The
every kind.
While others might focus on different values from those just mentioned, Naess’s
approach has much to offer, not least its stress on self-realization and its globally
inclusive scope. But his ‘Deep Ecology’ platform also includes some controversial
For Naess, my true self is not confined to my physical body, but (because everything
greater Self that I am (supposedly) obliged to defend. But this move seems to take
identification far too far. Besides, many people find that tracts of nature are well
worth defending even if they do not identify with nature in this way. For there are
plenty of other motivations, such as respect, admiration, and wanting our successors
the human population. This tenet was thought to be needed to allow room for the
continued flourishing of other species. But it also led some of Naess’s followers
(though not Naess himself) to welcome catastrophes like famines, and the consequent
decrease in human numbers they were expected to bring. Others were inclined to
reject any platform capable of carrying such implications. We should perhaps respond
Rolston’s contribution
Rolston III’s early essay ‘Is There an Ecological Ethic?’ (1975). Rolston (an
philosophy) was concerned to explain why we ought, for example, to recycle, and
thus how to get from facts and scientific laws to conclusions that hinge around an
David Hume. But Rolston was able to suggest more than one solution for the
recycling example he had selected. A first possible solution is that (ultimately) human
that human life is itself valuable. This approach makes recycling a matter of fostering
human interests, and (Rolston would say) embodies humanist rather than ecological
values. However, Rolston’s preferred solution instead says that we should recycle
because this promotes ecosystem integrity, and ecosystem integrity has value in itself,
or intrinsic value.
Much could be said to elucidate the notion of ecosystem integrity. It may suffice to
say that this would involve healthy, functioning ecosystems, both incorporating and
supporting interacting living organisms and their cycles of life. Here, Rolston’s
But Rolston was also drawing attention to the need for environmental ethics to adopt
an understanding of value that does not stop short at what is valuable merely as a
means (like money and resources), and instead goes on to identify what is valuable for
its own sake. A fairly uncontroversial example of something valuable for its own sake
is health.
Nearly everyone takes it for granted that something or other is valuable for its own
sake. Very few people seriously believe that nothing at all has this character.
Rolston’s distinctive suggestion is that an ecological ethic might stand out from other
One common feature of the contributions of Routley, Naess, and Rolston was their
Yet the issue soon arose of whether you can study environmental ethics at all if you
endorse such an anthropocentric approach, or whether you are disqualified before you
begin. But subjects of study should not be defined by ideological stances, and in any
case one of the reasons for environmentally-friendly activities like recycling could
So, while many of us may wish to support one or another ampler and broader value-
from the community of environmental ethicists, and certainly not to exclude them by
definition. Such thinkers often call themselves ‘pragmatists’, and some, such as Bryan
One issue raised by these early thinkers was the question of which beings matter
where ethics is concerned, and should be taken into account when decisions are being
made. To use different language, this is the question of the scope of moral standing.
12
One cogent answer to this question has been supplied by Kenneth Goodpaster:
whatever has a good of its own and can be benefited. For bestowing benefits is central
to morality. In other words, all living organisms have moral standing. Stances of this
kind have been called ‘biocentric’ ones, in emphatic contrast to the ‘anthropocentric’
shortly.
A further issue concerns whether, and how much, future interests count. (Naess’s
essay in particular raises this matter.) Aristotle thought that including these interests
would make ethics too complicated. But the effects of modern technology are often
them. So the future impacts of current actions should be taken into account where
they can be foreseen. In this context, Hans Jonas has argued (in The Imperative of
ethics itself.
Yet most economists believe in discounting future goods and bads so that they count
for less than present ones. They have some good reasons, because (for example) some
future impacts are uncertain. But philosophers have tended to respond that
discounting should be limited to cases where these reasons can be seen to apply, and
not applied across the board, or blanketwise. Future injuries and future pollution will
be just as bad as present cases, and, when foreseeable, should be treated just as
seriously.
13
Another issue, raised seminally by Rolston (and touched on already in the previous
section of this chapter), concerns what has value not as a means (or instrumentally)
but in itself (or intrinsically). Things of this kind will be what give moral ‘oughts’
their point. One possible answer is the flourishing of human beings. But if we accept
that other living creatures also have moral standing, then the flourishing of these
Some philosophers have reservations about the very concept of intrinsic value. But if
anything has value of any other sort, then something must have intrinsic value (value
that is not derivative from something else). For if nothing had such value, then
nothing would have value at all. And while human happiness or flourishing is usually
agreed to be one such ‘something’, reflection on the themes discussed in this chapter
One final issue concerns the question of the grounds for preserving species and
ecosystems. Some environmental ethicists suggest that these entities must be held to
greater importance to preserving the last members of a species than (like numbers of)
is correct. But it could instead be due to the moral standing and intrinsic value of
ones. So biocentrism can answer this question too. Similar reasoning is relevant to
ecosystems.
14
Anthropocentrism can also answer this question, but only for species and ecosystems
that are beneficial to humanity. Arguably, though, many are not. Does this mean that
there is no case for preserving them? The answer to this question may allow you, the