Liberalismo, Individualidad e Identidad
Liberalismo, Individualidad e Identidad
This essay began in response to challenges from Tom Nagel, Ronnie Dworkin, and
Richard Bernstein to say more about various aspects of the ethics of identity. I am grateful
to them. I also owe a debt to the editors of this journal and to Jorge Garcia, whose written
comments helped me revise this essay. I had the opportunity to discuss this essay at Vander-
bilt University (where it started out as the Harry Howard Jr. Lecture in the Humanities),
Rutgers University, University College, London, Harvard Law School's Legal Theory Semi-
nar, the National Humanities Center, and the New York Humanities Institute. I wish I had
been able to integrate more of the many insights I gained from these discussions, especially
since I learned in all these places how many of my claims invite debate.
1. Quoted in Ernest La Jeunesse, Andre Gide, and Franz Blei, In MemoriamOscar
Wilde,trans. Percival Pollard (Greenwich, Conn., 1905), p. 49. See also Gide, 29 June 1913,
TheJournals ofAndre Gide, trans. Justin O'Brien, 4 vols. (New York, 1947), 1:339.
2. Michel Foucault, "On the Genealogy of Ethics," Ethics: Subjectivityand Truth,vol. 1
of TheEssential Worksof Foucault, ed. Paul Rabinow (New York, 1997), p. 262.
305
case L, in the way in which Republican and Democrat begin with a big R
and a big D when they refer to the parties. But in philosophy we have
come to use the word liberalismwith a lower-case L to refer to a particular
tradition in politics and the philosophy of politics whose central ideas
would probably be endorsed by most people in the four political parties
in Britain and the United States that I have just mentioned. In the sense
in which I am discussing the term, just as American electoral politicians
are all small-r republicans and small-d democrats, British politicians are
all small-I liberals. Indeed, if there were a word for the consensus within
which electoral politics are debated in the industrialized world today, it
might as well be liberalism, even if there are some who reject the term
because it has associations they do not care for.
If you are a philosopher, consensus doesn't always make you happy.
Nietzsche once made a remark to the effect that the consensussapientium-
the agreement of the wise-might be evidence of untruth.3 As usual, he
was exaggerating. But the fact that everybody seems to agree about some-
thing isn't always proof that we're right. And even if we are right, it may
do us good to think about the principles, the values and ideals, that un-
derlie our agreement, not just to make the consensus more intellectually
secure, but also to explore consequences we haven't noticed. To start such
an exploration of consensus, however, we first need to say something
about the liberal tradition.
It seems to me there are two obvious ways of going about saying what
you mean by liberalism. One is historical. It is to point to the development
over the last few centuries, but especially since the American and French
Revolutions, of a new form of political life. This form of life finds expres-
sion in certain political institutions: among them, on the one hand, re-
publicanism, or at least constitutional rather than absolute monarchy,
elected rather than hereditary rulers, and, more generally, some sort of
appeal to the consent of the governed; and, on the other hand, a legal
system that respects certain fundamental rights, limiting the power of
those who govern. These civil or political rights carve out for citizens a
corresponding sphere of freedoms including those of political speech, the
press, and religion. Each of these elements can come on its own. There
were republics in Europe as far back as Athens; the first German emper-
ors were elected;4 and freedom of the press and religious toleration devel-
oped in England within a monarchical scheme. What characterizes the
beginnings of liberalism is, then, a combination of political institutions:
constitutions, rights, elections, and protections for private property. In
the twentieth century, in both Europe and North America, there was
added to the recognition of these political rights a concern to guarantee
certain minimum conditions of welfare for every citizen, what we call-
even if the extension of the term rightsin this way is a little controversial-
economic and social rights. And it is that combination of civil rights and
welfare provision that is identified in the United States as the liberal and
in Europe as the social democratic tradition.
But the liberal form of life was characterized not only by institutions
but also by a rhetoric, a body of ideas and arguments, which received
their most familiar expression for us here in these United States in these,
the most familiar words of the American Declaration of Independence of
1776:
passage are captured quite succinctly in the rallying cry of the French
revolutionaries: libert6,egaliti, fraternitW.
Liberty and equality are there in the American Declaration, on its
face, so to speak. But fraternity is there too, for fraternity is what binds
together the people, the people who may alter or abolish forms of govern-
ment. The Declaration takes for granted that there is already an Ameri-
can people to exercise this right. The American Revolution assumes, with
an assurance that is surely bold in a multireligious immigrant country in
the New World, that there is a nation here that can construct an American
government. This is particularly striking since there were important as-
sumptions made by the country's founders about who the we of "we, the
people" were. John Jay in the second of the FederalistPapers blithely ig-
nores most of the difficulties when he tells us that he has
often taken notice that Providence has been pleased to give this one
connected country to one united people-a people descended from
the same ancestors, speaking the same language, professing the same
religion, attached to the same principles of government, very similar
in their manners and customs, and who, by their joint counsels,
arms, and efforts, fighting side by side throughout a long and bloody
war, have nobly established their general liberty and independence.5
This passage puts aside the fact of the Indian, African, Jewish, and Catho-
lic presence in the American colonies. Indeed, it might seem to exclude
from the people (given the limited role of women in the actual fighting
during the War of Independence) most, if not all, women. After all, it was
only in the mid-nineteenth century that "we, the people" came to include
African Americans; and, if suffrage is an expression of our fraternity, then
women were not fully joined to the nation until this century. Only when
fraternity is linked to sorority is the process complete.
Many people nowadays will still find most of the ideas in these early
sentences of the Declaration something close to self-evident (even those
who doubt that it was a Creator who endowed us with our rights). Clearly,
these sentiments were far from uncontroversial when they were first pro-
nounced. Edmund Burke, who was as profound a student of constitu-
tional history as England produced in this age of revolutions, made some
of the obvious objections at the start.
First of all, he asked, doesn't the value of liberty depend on what you
do with it? Or, as he put it in the Reflectionson the Revolutionin France:
Burke uses the word honor-rather than dignity, esteem,or respect-in his
response to this notion of equality; in his day it was obvious that honor,
like dignity, was something that only some people had. (Even radical old
Wise thought that in civil society there must be "just distinctions among
men of honor." [V,p. 128])8 So that, once again, Burke makes what was,
in the context, the obvious objection:
Questions such as, How can everyone have dignity? and Why is lib-
erty a good thing? arose, then, in the course of the development of the
political institutions of liberalism. They suggest the second way into an
understanding of liberalism, which is to explore its philosophical founda-
tions. Such inquiry seeks to answer Burke's challenges by developing a
general picture of human life that includes government and politics but
also, perhaps, other forms of association.
Burke's answer to questions about the justification of political institu-
tions was what came to be called conservative, as, in the first half of the
nineteenth century, conservativeand liberalbecame standard ways of divid-
ing up the world of political opinion.10 (Eventually, these positions were
codified as Right and Left according to where the proponents of the two
8. John Locke, who is accounted one of the fathers of the spirit of the American Revo-
lution, used the word dignity in the same way Burke would have, to mean the special privi-
leges of people of standing.
9. Burke has a lovely little footnote here, in which he cites the Old Testament: "Ecclesi-
asticus 38: 24, 25. 'The wisdom of a learned man cometh by opportunity of leisure: and he
that hath little business shall become wise. How can he get wisdom that holdeth the plough,
and the glorieth in the goad; that driveth oxen, and is occupied in their labors, and whose
talk is of bullocks?'" (Burke, Reflectionson the Revolutionin France, 3:296).
10. Identifying the institutional and intellectual antecedents of modern liberalism is a
separate task from exploring the history of the word liberalismand its cognates in various
other European languages. Modern liberalism draws on ideas such as those enumerated by
Kant and Locke and practices such as the provision of constitutional rights that were devel-
oped well before the word liberal ever became associated with them. Reputedly, the first
political group that called themselves "liberales" was in Spain in the early nineteenth cen-
tury; Constant began to refer to his political ideas as liberal in the late eighteenth century.
(I owe these historical observations to the conversation after my talk at University College,
London.)
Burke asked why we should think all people were entitled to equal
respect: the working tallow-chandler, his wife, the King of England, all of
them. Many answers have been offered to that question. John Wise, the
radical Protestant divine whom I quoted earlier, answered "that we all
derive our being from one stock, the same common father of [the] human
race," and that we all come into and go out of the world in much the same
way: "Death observes no ceremony, but knocks as loud at the barriers of
the Court as at the door of the cottage" (V,p. 129). Immanuel Kant fa-
mously argued that our equality was grounded in our shared human ca-
pacity for reason. In proposing his story, which was a view not just about
politics but about the whole of moral life, he developed the idea of auton-
omy: the idea of a person's being self-governing, ruling him- or herself,
rather than being ruled from outside, heteronomously, by other forces or
other people.
But I am going to start my exploration of the liberal vision with John
Stuart Mill, who argued some decades after Burke in his still bracing essay
On Liberty(1859) that it is our capacity to use all our faculties in individual
ways that gives us the right to freedom. In the third chapter "On Individ4
uality, as One of the Elements of Wellbeing," he writes, near the start:
11. John Stuart Mill, On Liberty(Amherst, Mass., 1986), p. 65; hereafter abbreviated OL.
He who lets the world, or his own portion of it, choose his plan of
life for him, has no need for any other faculty than the ape-like one
of imitation. He who chooses his plan for himself, employs all his
faculties. He must use observation to see, reasoning and judgment
to foresee, activity to gather materials for decision, discrimination to
decide, and when he has decided, firmness and self-control to hold to
his deliberate decision. And these qualities he requires and exercises
exactly in proportion as the part of his conduct which he determines
according to his own judgment and feelings is a large one. ... Hu-
man nature is not a machine to be built after a model, and set to do
exactly the work prescribed for it, but a tree, which requires to grow
... according to the tendency of the inward forces which make it a
living thing. [OL, pp. 67-68]
individualities. But I think it is best to read Mill as arguing not just for
diversity-being different-but in fact for self-creation, as claiming that
such an enterprise is, in itself, a good. For I might choose a plan of life
that was, as it happened, very like somebody else's and still not be merely
aping them, following them blindly as a model. I wouldn't, then, be con-
tributing to diversity (so, in one sense, I wouldn't be very individual), but
I would still be constructing my own-in another sense, individual-plan
of life. On Libertydefends freedom from government because only free
people can take full command of their own lives.
More generally, I don't think Mill is very clear in On Libertyabout
how what he calls individuality might relate to other kinds of goods. But
reading Mill can lead you to think that sometimes something matters be-
cause someone has chosen to make a life in which it matters and that it
would not matter if they had not chosen to make such a life. If this formu-
lation seems abstract, it is because Mill speaks abstractly; it will help to
imagine a more concrete example.
Consider, then, Mr. Stevens, the butler in Kazuo Ishiguro's novel The
Remains of the Day (played by Anthony Hopkins's in the book's film ver-
sion).13 Mr. Stevens has spent a whole life in service in a "great house,"
and his aim has been to perform his task to the very best of his ability.
He sees himself as fitting into the world as part of the machinery that
made the life of his master, Lord Darlington, possible. Since his master
has acted on the stage of public history, he sees Lord Darlington's public
acts as part of what gives meaning to his own life. As he puts it:
Mr. Stevens takes what is "within [his] realm" extremely seriously; for
example, he feels, as he says, "uplifted" by a "sense of triumph" when he
manages to pursue his duties unflustered on the evening that the woman
he loves has announced to him that she is going to marry somebody else
(R, p. 228). By the time (well into the book) he tells us about this fateful
day, we know him well enough to understand how such a sentiment is
possible.
At the end of the book, Mr. Stevens is returning to Darlington House
from the holiday in which he has reviewed his life with us, and he tells us
13. Kazuo Ishiguro, TheRemainsof the Day (New York, 1989); hereafter abbreviated R.
Now I am sure no one who reads this essay will have the ambition to
be a butler, certainly not the sort of butler that Mr. Stevens aimed to be.
And there is, indeed, something mildly ridiculous in the thought of an
elderly man working on his skills at light conversation in order to enter-
tain his young "master."Readers are likely to feel when they come to these
last words a tremendous sadness at what is missing from Mr. Stevens's
life. Nevertheless, Mr. Stevens is continuing to live out the life he has
chosen. It does seem to me that we can understand part of what Mill is
suggesting by saying that bantering is something of value to Mr. Stevens
because he has chosen to be the best butler he can be. This is not a life
we would have chosen, but for someone who has chosen it, it is intelligible
that improving one's bantering skills is a good.
To say that bantering is of value to Mr. Stevens is not just to say that
he wants to be able to do it well, as he might want to be good at bowling
or chess. It is to say that, given his aims, given what Mill calls his "plan of
life," bantering matters to him; we, for whom bantering does not matter,
or to whom it does not matter in this way, can still see that it is a value for
him within the life he has chosen.
You may think that this is not a life that anyone who had other rea-
sonable options should have chosen and that even someone who was
forced into it should not have taken to it with the enthusiasm and com-
mitment that Mr. Stevens manifests. You might even explain this by say-
ing that the life of the perfect servant is not one of great dignity. But Mr.
Stevens knows a good deal about dignity, and he even offers a definition
of it in response to the questioning of a doctor he meets on his travels.
14. It is part of the brilliance of Ishiguro's characterization of Stevens that the butler
ends his account of himself with a split infinitive. Stevens, after all, is proud that he is taken
for a "gentleman," but a gentleman would have been taught to fuss about split infinitives
at school.
This is more than a joke. Mr. Stevens believesin decorum, good manners,
formality. These compose the world that he has chosen to inhabit and
make it the world it is. Once again, these may not be values for us, but
they are values for him, given his plan of life. When he is serious, when
he is explaining to a room full of villagers what makes the difference
between a gentleman and someone who is not, he says, "one would sus-
pect that the quality . .. might be most usefully termed 'dignity.'" And this
is a quality that he, like Burke, believes to be far from equally distributed.
"Dignity's not just something for gentlemen," says a character called
Harry Smith. And Mr. Stevens observes in his narrative voice: "I per-
ceived, of course, that Mr Harry Smith and I were rather at cross pur-
poses on this matter" (R, p. 186).
I like Mr. Stevens as an illustration of self-creation and individuality
as a value; to cite him as such is to read TheRemainsof the Day against the
grain. Ishiguro is like you and me, a modern person, and his novel is
deeply sad because Mr. Stevens's life is, in so many ways, a failure. It is a
failure, in part, because he is and intends to be servile. It is important
here that servility entails not acting as a servant-which is what Burke
plainly thought-but rather behaving like a slave. Servility isn'tjust hap-
pily earning your living by working for another; it's acting as an unfree
person, a person whose will is somehow subjected to another's. Unexcep-
tionally, I have very little enthusiasm for such a disposition (though there
are some who think it appropriate where the other in question is God.)'5
But in my opinion the novel cheats in its argument against this form of
servility. Ishiguro's depiction of Stevens obscures the relationship be-
tween dignity and individuality by conflating servant and slave; he pre-
vents us from seeing that it is servility, not service, that is undignified.
Lord Darlington turns out to be a weak man, an easy mark for the
National Socialist Ribbentrop, Germany's prewar ambassador to London.
The result is that Mr. Stevens's life is a failure because his master's has
proved one, not because service is, in fact, bound to lead to failure. After
all, if Mr. Stevens had been working for Winston Churchill, he at least
could have denied that he had failed; he could have claimed to have been
the faithful servant of a great man, just as he set out to be. Instead, Mr.
Stevens's vocation robs him of both his dignity and his love life, since the
only woman he might have married works in the same household, and
he believes a relationship with her would likely have compromised their
professional lives. Though Mr. Stevens makes a mess of this, there is no
reason to think that these losses are the fault of his vocation. In the end,
Mr. Stevens serves as a good example of the moral power of individuality
15. These observations on servility were prompted by comments from editors of this
journal. The reminder that "Thy way, not mine, Oh Lord" is a possible religious sentiment
I owe to Jorge Garcia (though it was not made in response to my comments about servility,
but as a protest against one reading of Frank Sinatra's lyric, which I discuss below!).
How are we to account for the thought that I have been using Mr.
Stevens to help us explore, the idea that, as I put it just now, sometimes
something matters because someone has chosen to make a life in which
it matters? This is more than the thought that what is good for people
depends on what they want. Mill was a sort of utilitarian and believed, in
general, that pleasure was good and pain bad (and also, unlike some
other utilitarians, that there were objectively higher kinds of pleasure
that mattered more than lower ones). So he certainly thought that be-
cause the satisfaction of desire brings pleasure (and its obstruction, pain)
what is good depends on what people desire.
But, as I say, the claim here is something more than that, and, in any
case, Mill commends it to us not as a utilitarian idea but as one that we
will recognize as correct without deriving it from a more general picture.
It is the claim that, having chosen a plan of life, certain aims internal to
that plan come to have value just because they follow from a plan we
ourselves have chosen. And it is a thought that applies to Mr. Stevens
even though he has chosen a life that makes sense only if dignity is not
(as he wrongly believes) something everyone shares equally. That, I think,
is one of the core thoughts in Mill'sarticulation of individuality as a value.
You can find Mill's view more explicitly stated in a later passage in
chapter three: "If a person possesses any tolerable amount of common
sense and experience, his own mode of laying out his existence is best,
not because it is the best in itself, but because it is his own mode" (OL,
pp. 77-78) It is easy to miss this point because Mill goes on, almost imme-
diately, to introduce a different idea.
Here, the idea is that freedom allows people to make the best of them-
selves, to cultivate their higher natures, and attain their full moral and
This life was good-the singer has "too few" regrets "to mention"--not
just because it was full but because it was lived his way. If my choosing it
is part of what makes my life plan good, then imposing on me a plan of
life-even one that is, in other respects, a good one-is depriving me of
a certain kind of good. Once you concede this premise, the argument for
liberty from government, from society, and even from family and friends
is pretty direct. We can answer Burke by saying that liberty allows more
than doing what one pleases; it allows one to shape a plan of life that is
an expression of one's own creativity and to live, then, according not only
to general values-truthfulness, kindness, and the rest, which should be
part of every life-but also in the light of values that flow from one's own
plan. And we can say, with Mill, that it is intrinsically good, other things
being equal, when people live according to their own plan.
The popularity of "My Way" suggests that many people nowadays
share Mill's conviction. And so I want to underline how different this view
is from the view that Burke caricatures as the project of doing as one
pleases. A plan of life here serves as a way of integrating one's purposes
over time, of fitting together the different things one values. That is part
16. Matthew Arnold, Cultureand Anarchy, ed. Samuel Lipman (New Haven, Conn.,
1994), p. 36.
17. Frank Sinatra, "My Way,"WEA/Warner Brothers, 1969. The lyrics are by Paul
Anka.
of why a goal that flows from such a plan has more value than the mere
satisfaction of a fleeting desire. It isn'tjust any desire but one that matters
because it fits into a wider picture. But Mill says that it matters also be-
cause, in effect, the life plan is an expression of my individuality, of who
I am. And in this sense, a desire that flows from a value that itself derives
from a life plan is more important than a desire (such as an appetite) that
I just happen to have; for it flows from my reflective choices, not just
passing fancy.
yourself matter most. Yet a plan of life for Mill was likely to include family
and friends and might include (as his did) public service. Mill is not ar-
guing for self-cultivation at the expense of sociability. He is arguing for
self-cultivation, for a view of one's self as a project, in a way that seems to
suggest, perhaps, that self-cultivation and sociability are competing val-
ues, though each has its place. This can lead us to think that the good of
individuality is reined in by or traded-off against the goods of sociability
so that there is an intrinsic opposition between the self and society. This
matters for political theory because it can lead to the view that political
institutions, which develop and reflect the value of sociability, are always
sources of constraint on our individuality. Let me dub this the problem
of the unsociabilityof individualism.
These two concerns strike me as both plausible and important. A
credible defense of the value of individuality or self-creation requires that
we respond to them; to do so it is helpful, I think, to reframe Mill's under-
standing.
tant that we can see in Mr. Stevens's individual existence, which is that
what structures his sense of his life is less like a blueprint and more like
what we nowadays call an identity.
Mr. Stevens has constructed for himself an identity as a butler: more
specifically as the butler to Lord Darlington and of the Darlington House,
and as his father's son. It is an identity in which his gender plays a role
(butlers must be men) and in which his nationality is important, too, be-
cause in the late 1930s Lord Darlington meddles (rather incompetently,
it turns out) in the "great affairs of the" British "nation," and it is his ser-
vice to a man who is serving that nation that gives Mr. Stevens part of his
satisfaction (R, p. 199).
But Ishiguro's character has put these more generic identities-but-
ler, son, man, Englishman-together with other skills and capacities that
are more particular, and, in so doing, he has fashioned a self.
religion. What the collective dimensions have in common is that they are
what the philosopher Ian Hacking has dubbed kindsof person:men, gays,
Americans, Catholics, but also butlers, hairdressers, and philosophers.'18
Hacking's key insight about "kinds of persons" is that they are
brought into being by the creation of names for them. So he defends
what he calls a "dynamic nominalism," arguing "that numerous kinds of
human beings and human acts come into being hand in hand with our
invention of the categories labeling them" ("M,"p. 87).
Hacking begins from the philosophical truism, whose most influen-
tial formulation is in Elizabeth Anscombe's work on intention, that, in
intentional action, people act "under descriptions"; in other words, their
actions are conceptually shaped.19 (What I do is dependent on what I
think I am doing. To use a simple example, I have to have a wide range
of concepts for my writing my name in a certain way to count as "signing
a contract.") It follows that what I can do depends on what concepts I
have available to me; among the concepts that may shape my action is
the concept of a certain kind of person and the behavior appropriate to
a person of that kind. Mr. Stevens is driven, in thinking about whether
he should develop his bantering skills, by the thought that he is a butler
and that banter is a butler's sort of skill.
Hacking offers as an example Sartre's brilliant evocation in Being
and Nothingnessof another kind of service professional, the Parisian garfon
de cafit:
His movement is quick and forward, a little too precise, a little too
rapid. He comes towards the patrons with a step a little too quick.
He bends forward a little too eagerly, his eyes express an interest too
solicitous for the order of the customer. ["M,"p. 81]
Hacking comments:
18. See Ian Hacking, "Making Up People" in Formsof Desire: Sexual Orientationand
the Social ConstructionistControversy,ed. Edward Stein (New York, 1988), p. 74; hereafter
abbreviated "M."As Hacking would be the first to acknowledge, this insight is already pres-
ent in what sociologists call labeling theory. See Mary McIntosh, "The Homosexual Role,"
in Formsof Desire, pp. 25-42.
19. See G. E. M. Anscombe, Intention (Oxford, 1957).
The idea of the garfon de cafr lacks the sort of theoretical commit-
ments that are trailed by many of our social identities: black and white,
gay and straight, man and woman. So it makes no sense to ask of someone
who is employed as a garfon de cafr whether that is what he really is. Be-
cause we have expectations of the garfon de cafi, it is a recognizable iden-
tity. But those expectations are about the performance of the role; they
depend on our assumption of intentional conformity to the expectations.
With other identities, however-and here the familiar collectives of
race, ethnicity, gender, and the rest come back into view-the expecta-
tions we have are not based simply on the idea that those who have these
identities are playing out a role. Rightly or wrongly, we do not normally
think of the expectations we have of men or women as being simply the
result of the fact that there are conventions about how men and women
behave.
Once labels are applied to people, ideas about people who fit the
label come to have social and psychological effects. In particular, these
ideas shape the ways people conceive of themselves and their projects. So
the labels operate to mold what we may call identification,the process
through which individuals intentionally shape their projects-including
their plans for their own lives and their conceptions of the good life-by
reference to available labels, available identities. In identification, I shape
my life by the thought that something is an appropriate aim or an appro-
priate way of acting for an American, a black man, a philosopher. It seems
right to call this identificationbecause the label plays a role in shaping the
way the agent makes decisions about how to conduct a life, in the process
of the construction of one's identity.
Thus, as I have argued elsewhere, every collective identity seems to
have the following sort of structure: there is a label, L, associated with
descriptive criteria-ascriptions- that lead to expectations(which may be
grounded in norms) about how Ls will behave; there are identificationsby
Ls, so that they sometimes act as Ls; and, finally, there are consequences
in the way that people treat Ls (so that sometimes they are treated as Ls).20
These"asLs"-acting as an L, being treated as an L-connect identities to
conceptions of what Ls are or should be like.
In the case of the garfon de cafi, conventions of behavior associated
with a role are explicitly central. The ascriptions are based on the simple
idea that someone who works in caf6s of a certain sort will conform to
spond to, nothing out of which to construct. The reasonable middle view
is that constructing an identity is a good but that the identity must make
some kind of sense. And for it to make sense, as both Mr. Stevens and the
examples of race or gay identity suggest, it must be an identity con-
structed in response to facts outside oneself, things that are beyond one's
own choices. Some philosophers--Sartre among them-have tried to
combine both the romantic and the existentialist views. Michel Foucault
suggested as much some years ago:
I think that from the theoretical point of view, Sartre avoids the idea
of the self as something that is given to us, but through the moral
notion of authenticity, he turns back to the idea that we have to be
ourselves-to be truly our true self. I think the only acceptable prac-
tical consequence of what Sartre has said is to link his theoretical
insight to the practice of creativity-and not to that of authenticity.
From the idea that the self is not given to us, I think there is only
one practical consequence: we have to create ourselves as a work of
art. In his analyses of Baudelaire, Flaubert and so on, it is interesting
to see that Sartre refers the work of creation to a certain relation to
oneself-the author to himself-which has the form of authenticity
or inauthenticity. I would like to say exactly the contrary: we should
not have to refer the creative activity of somebody to the kind of
relation he has to himself, but should relate the kind of relation one
has to oneself to a creative activity.21
together a life. This would not be a world of creativity but a flat and
boring dystopia. Nietzsche articulated the view that explains why this life
would be meaningless:
Thinking about what history has, in fact, given each of us, as materi-
als for our identities, will also allow us to speak to the supposed unsocia-
bility of the liberal self. The language of identity allows us to remind
ourselves how much it is true that we are, in Charles Taylor's elegant
formulation, "dialogically" constituted. Beginning in infancy, it is in dia-
logue with other people's understandings of who I am that I develop a
conception of my own identity. We come into the world "mewling and
puking in our mother's arms" (as Shakespeare so genially put it) capable
of human individuality, but only if we have the chance to develop it in
interaction with others. An identity is always articulated through con-
cepts (and practices) made available to you by religion, society, school,
and state, mediated by family, peers, friends. Dialogue shapes the identi-
ties we develop as we grow up, but the very material out of which we
make it is provided, in part, by our society, by what Taylor has called our
language in "a broad sense." It "cover[s] not only the words we speak, but
also other modes of expression whereby we define ourselves, including
the 'languages' of art, of gesture, of love, and the like."23It follows that
the self whose choices liberalism celebrates is not a presocial thing-not
some authentic inner essence independent of the human world into
22. Nietzsche, The Gay Science, trans. and ed. Walter Kaufmann (New York, 1974),
p. 232.
23. Charles Taylor, "The Politics of Recognition," in Multiculturalism:Examining "The
Politicsof Recognition,"ed. Gutmann (Princeton, N.J., 1994), p. 32.
I have been arguing that collective identities (that is, the collective
dimensions of our individual identities) are responses to something out-
side ourselves. They are the products of histories, and our engagement
with them invokes capacities that are not under our control. But they are
also social, not just in the sense that they involve others, but also because
they are constituted in part by socially transmitted conceptions of how a
proper person of that identity behaves. In constructing an identity one
draws, among other things, on the kinds of person available in one's soci-
ety. Of course, there is not just one way that gay or straight people or
blacks or whites or men or women are to behave, but there are ideas
around (contested, many of them, but all sides in these contests shape
our options) about how gay, straight, black, white, masculine, or feminine
people ought to behave. These notions provide loose norms or models,
which play a role in shaping the plans of life of those who make these
collective identities central to their individual identities. Collective identi-
ties, in short, provide what we might call scripts: narratives that people
can use in shaping their life plans and in telling their life stories.
It is important to acknowledge how much our personal histories, the
stories we tell of where we have been and where we are going, are con-
structed, like novels and movies, short stories and folk tales, within narra-
tive conventions. Indeed, one of the things that film or literature does for
us is to provide models for telling our lives. But part of the function of
our collective identities-of the whole repertory of them that a society
24. See my "Identity, Authenticity, Survival: Multicultural Societies and Social Repro-
duction," in Multiculturalism,pp. 149-63.
I hope I have persuaded you that you already think that identity-
as I have been explaining it-matters. But how does identity fit into our
broader moral projects?
One view is this: There are many things of value in the world. Their
value is objective; they are important whether or not anybody recognizes
25. This isn't to say that cleverness isn't a social product; it obviously is. You couldn't
be clever if you grew up like Kaspar Hauser. Nor is it to say that the social significance of
cleverness isn't the result of social practices, attitudes, and shared beliefs.
26. I am grateful to Garcia for pointing out to me that my initial formulation of this
point relied on a notion of intrinsic value that was, at best, unhelpful.
freedom down the path to the Gulag. But there are simple cases that
should remind us that enabling people to construct and live out an iden-
tity does not have to go awry.
Governments do, for example, provide public education in many
countries that helps children who do not yet know what their identity is
or what projects, hopes, and dreams they have for their lives. This is more
than negative liberty, more than government's getting out of the way. You
may say that parents could do this; in principle, they could. But suppose
they won't or can't? Shouldn't society step in, in the name of individuality
and identity, to insist that children be prepared for life as free adults?
And, in our society, won't that require them to be able to read? To know
the language or languages of their community? To be able to assess argu-
ments, interpret traditions? And even if the parents are trying to provide
all these things, isn't there a case for society, through the state, offering
them positive support?
Or take welfare provision, which I mentioned at the start. I have
argued that individuality is a matter of developing a life in response to
the materials provided by your capacities and your social world (and,
more particularly, the social identities embedded in it). Liberalism says
we should create a politics that allows people to do this. But there can be
obstacles to the realization of our individuality other than the limitations
of law. Can people really construct dignified individual lives in a modern
world where there is no frontier to conquer, no empty land to cultivate,
unless they have certain material resources? Can people be said to be free
to develop their individuality if they are sick and unable to afford treat-
ment that will free them from it?
What holds together the desire to educate children, provide welfare
for the poor, and give physical assistance to the handicapped who need
it is the idea that education, welfare, and assistance of these sorts frees
people to develop lives worth living. Berlin was skeptical about this be-
cause he wondered who would decide what a life worth living was. But,
as we have seen, Mill already had an answer to that question: "If a person
possesses any tolerable amount of common sense and experience, his own
mode of laying out his existence is best."
There are hard questions here about fairness (my dreams may be
expensive, taxation may be burdensome). People are coerced into provid-
ing resources for governments to spend and may thereby be limited in
their capacity to make the lives they have chosen. That I do not deny. But
hard questions can be questions worth a hard look. And to refuse any
notion of positive liberty is to escape these questions only by refusing to
face them.
I have been suggesting one reason for the liberal faith in allowing
people to make their own lives. That argument is only one of the many
I think Austin's strategy for understanding freedom of the will can turn
out to be helpful in thinking about human dignity. Forjust as it is harder
to say what makes an act free than to list things that make it unfree, so,
while we cannot easily give a positive account of dignity, we can point to
cases where it is lacking. We know these cases because we have learned
about them over history and in our individual lives; a slave, we learned
over too long and bloody a struggle, cannot lead a dignified existence.
Mr. Stevens troubles us because he is in some ways like a slave. He is
servile; his servility reflects false beliefs and leaves him unable to (or dis-
suades him from trying to) understand Lord Darlington's attempts to rec-
oncile the English government to Hitler.
But slavery is not the only obstacle to dignity. In the modern world
a life with neither job nor money cannot be a life of dignity. We have also
learned that a life of handouts is not dignified either, and we are strug-
gling to find a reasonable middle way between demeaning handouts and
forced labor. People with severe physical disabilities have taught us in
recent years that we need to reshape public space if they are to enter it
with the dignity they deserve. Feminism has taught us for over more than
a century that dignity for women requires both that we respect the identi-
ties of individual women and that we do not bar them from a public
sphere. Gay and lesbian movements have taught us, building on the black
power movement, that dignity cannot come to those who are forced to
leave what matters most to them about themselves locked away in a pri-
vate realm. In many of these cases, identity matters. But at the end of an
essay that has focused on identity, it is right to insist that for liberalism it
is not the only thing that matters.