Trump v. United States
Trump v. United States
Trump v. United States
Syllabus
Syllabus
Syllabus
Syllabus
Syllabus
Branch, and to enable the President to carry out his constitutional du-
ties without undue caution. At a minimum, the President must be
immune from prosecution for an official act unless the Government can
show that applying a criminal prohibition to that act would pose no
“dangers of intrusion on the authority and functions of the Executive
Branch.” Fitzgerald, 457 U. S., at 754. Pp. 12–15.
(3) As for a President’s unofficial acts, there is no immunity. Alt-
hough Presidential immunity is required for official actions to ensure
that the President’s decisionmaking is not distorted by the threat of
future litigation stemming from those actions, that concern does not
support immunity for unofficial conduct. Clinton, 520 U. S., at 694,
and n. 19. The separation of powers does not bar a prosecution predi-
cated on the President’s unofficial acts. P. 15.
(b) The first step in deciding whether a former President is entitled
to immunity from a particular prosecution is to distinguish his official
from unofficial actions. In this case, no court thus far has drawn that
distinction, in general or with respect to the conduct alleged in partic-
ular. It is therefore incumbent upon the Court to be mindful that it is
“a court of final review and not first view.” Zivotofsky v. Clinton, 566
U. S. 189, 201. Critical threshold issues in this case are how to differ-
entiate between a President’s official and unofficial actions, and how
to do so with respect to the indictment’s extensive and detailed allega-
tions covering a broad range of conduct. The Court offers guidance on
those issues. Pp. 16–32.
(1) When the President acts pursuant to “constitutional and stat-
utory authority,” he takes official action to perform the functions of his
office. Fitzgerald, 456 U. S., at 757. Determining whether an action
is covered by immunity thus begins with assessing the President’s au-
thority to take that action. But the breadth of the President’s “discre-
tionary responsibilities” under the Constitution and laws of the United
States frequently makes it “difficult to determine which of [his] innu-
merable ‘functions’ encompassed a particular action.” Id., at 756. The
immunity the Court has recognized therefore extends to the “outer pe-
rimeter” of the President’s official responsibilities, covering actions so
long as they are “not manifestly or palpably beyond [his] authority.”
Blassingame v. Trump, 87 F. 4th 1, 13 (CADC).
In dividing official from unofficial conduct, courts may not inquire
into the President’s motives. Such a “highly intrusive” inquiry would
risk exposing even the most obvious instances of official conduct to ju-
dicial examination on the mere allegation of improper purpose. Fitz-
gerald, 457 U. S., at 756. Nor may courts deem an action unofficial
merely because it allegedly violates a generally applicable law. Oth-
erwise, Presidents would be subject to trial on “every allegation that
an action was unlawful,” depriving immunity of its intended effect.
Cite as: 603 U. S. ____ (2024) 5
Syllabus
Syllabus
Syllabus
Syllabus
No. 23–939
_________________
——————
1 Trump contends that the indictment stretches Section 1512(c)(2) “far
Nixon. The danger is akin to, indeed greater than, what led
us to recognize absolute Presidential immunity from civil
damages liability—that the President would be chilled from
taking the “bold and unhesitating action” required of an in-
dependent Executive. Fitzgerald, 457 U. S., at 745. Alt-
hough the President might be exposed to fewer criminal
prosecutions than the range of civil damages suits that
might be brought by various plaintiffs, the threat of trial,
judgment, and imprisonment is a far greater deterrent. Po-
tential criminal liability, and the peculiar public oppro-
brium that attaches to criminal proceedings, are plainly
more likely to distort Presidential decisionmaking than the
potential payment of civil damages.
The hesitation to execute the duties of his office fearlessly
and fairly that might result when a President is making de-
cisions under “a pall of potential prosecution,” McDonnell v.
United States, 579 U. S. 550, 575 (2016), raises “unique
risks to the effective functioning of government,” Fitzger-
ald, 457 U. S., at 751. A President inclined to take one
course of action based on the public interest may instead
opt for another, apprehensive that criminal penalties may
befall him upon his departure from office. And if a former
President’s official acts are routinely subjected to scrutiny
in criminal prosecutions, “the independence of the Execu-
tive Branch” may be significantly undermined. Vance, 591
U. S., at 800. The Framers’ design of the Presidency did not
envision such counterproductive burdens on the “vigor[]”
and “energy” of the Executive. The Federalist No. 70, at
471–472.
We must, however, “recognize[ ] the countervailing inter-
ests at stake.” Vance, 591 U. S., at 799. Federal criminal
laws seek to redress “a wrong to the public” as a whole, not
just “a wrong to the individual.” Huntington v. Attrill, 146
U. S. 657, 668 (1892). There is therefore a compelling “pub-
lic interest in fair and effective law enforcement.” Vance,
591 U. S., at 808. The President, charged with enforcing
14 TRUMP v. UNITED STATES
decide it. “[O]ne case” in more than “two centuries does not
afford enough experience” to definitively and comprehen-
sively determine the President’s scope of immunity from
criminal prosecution. Mazars, 591 U. S., at 871.
C
As for a President’s unofficial acts, there is no immunity.
The principles we set out in Clinton v. Jones confirm as
much. When Paula Jones brought a civil lawsuit against
then-President Bill Clinton for acts he allegedly committed
prior to his Presidency, we rejected his argument that he
enjoyed temporary immunity from the lawsuit while serv-
ing as President. 520 U. S., at 684. Although Presidential
immunity is required for official actions to ensure that the
President’s decisionmaking is not distorted by the threat of
future litigation stemming from those actions, that concern
does not support immunity for unofficial conduct. Id., at
694, and n. 19. The “ ‘justifying purposes’ ” of the immunity
we recognized in Fitzgerald, and the one we recognize to-
day, are not that the President must be immune because he
is the President; rather, they are to ensure that the Presi-
dent can undertake his constitutionally designated func-
tions effectively, free from undue pressures or distortions.
520 U. S., at 694, and n. 19 (quoting Fitzgerald, 457 U. S.,
at 755). “[I]t [is] the nature of the function performed, not
the identity of the actor who perform[s] it, that inform[s]
our immunity analysis.” Forrester v. White, 484 U. S. 219,
229 (1988). The separation of powers does not bar a prose-
cution predicated on the President’s unofficial acts.2
——————
2 Our decision in Clinton permitted claims alleging unofficial acts to
proceed against the sitting President. See 520 U. S., at 684. In the crim-
inal context, however, the Justice Department “has long recognized” that
“the separation of powers precludes the criminal prosecution of a sitting
President.” Brief for United States 9 (citing A Sitting President’s Ame-
nability to Indictment and Criminal Prosecution, 24 Op. OLC 222 (2000);
emphasis deleted); see Tr. for Oral Arg. 78.
16 TRUMP v. UNITED STATES
III
Determining whether a former President is entitled to
immunity from a particular prosecution requires applying
the principles we have laid out to his conduct at issue. The
first step is to distinguish his official from unofficial actions.
In this case, however, no court has thus far considered how
to draw that distinction, in general or with respect to the
conduct alleged in particular.
Despite the unprecedented nature of this case, and the
very significant constitutional questions that it raises, the
lower courts rendered their decisions on a highly expedited
basis. Because those courts categorically rejected any form
of Presidential immunity, they did not analyze the conduct
alleged in the indictment to decide which of it should be cat-
egorized as official and which unofficial. Neither party has
briefed that issue before us (though they discussed it at oral
argument in response to questions). And like the underly-
ing immunity question, that categorization raises multiple
unprecedented and momentous questions about the powers
of the President and the limits of his authority under the
Constitution. As we have noted, there is little pertinent
precedent on those subjects to guide our review of this
case—a case that we too are deciding on an expedited basis,
less than five months after we granted the Government’s
request to construe Trump’s emergency application for a
stay as a petition for certiorari, grant that petition, and an-
swer the consequential immunity question. See 601 U. S.,
at ___. Given all these circumstances, it is particularly in-
cumbent upon us to be mindful of our frequent admonition
that “[o]urs is a court of final review and not first view.”
Zivotofsky v. Clinton, 566 U. S. 189, 201 (2012) (internal
quotation marks omitted).
Critical threshold issues in this case are how to differen-
tiate between a President’s official and unofficial actions,
and how to do so with respect to the indictment’s extensive
and detailed allegations covering a broad range of conduct.
Cite as: 603 U. S. ____ (2024) 17
instance, excluding “any mention” of the official act associated with the
bribe “would hamstring the prosecution.” Post, at 6 (opinion concurring
in part); cf. post, at 25–27 (opinion of SOTOMAYOR, J.). But of course the
prosecutor may point to the public record to show the fact that the Pres-
ident performed the official act. And the prosecutor may admit evidence
of what the President allegedly demanded, received, accepted, or agreed
to receive or accept in return for being influenced in the performance of
the act. See 18 U. S. C. §201(b)(2). What the prosecutor may not do,
however, is admit testimony or private records of the President or his
advisers probing the official act itself. Allowing that sort of evidence
would invite the jury to inspect the President’s motivations for his official
actions and to second-guess their propriety. As we have explained, such
inspection would be “highly intrusive” and would “ ‘seriously cripple’ ” the
President’s exercise of his official duties. Fitzgerald, 457 U. S., at 745,
756 (quoting Spalding v. Vilas, 161 U. S. 483, 498 (1896)); see supra, at
18. And such second-guessing would “threaten the independence or ef-
fectiveness of the Executive.” Trump v. Vance, 591 U. S. 786, 805 (2020).
Cite as: 603 U. S. ____ (2024) 33
ald, 457 U. S., at 758, n. 41. Like everyone else, the Presi-
dent is subject to prosecution in his unofficial capacity. But
unlike anyone else, the President is a branch of govern-
ment, and the Constitution vests in him sweeping powers
and duties. Accounting for that reality—and ensuring that
the President may exercise those powers forcefully, as the
Framers anticipated he would—does not place him above
the law; it preserves the basic structure of the Constitution
from which that law derives.
The dissents’ positions in the end boil down to ignoring
the Constitution’s separation of powers and the Court’s
precedent and instead fear mongering on the basis of ex-
treme hypotheticals about a future where the President
“feels empowered to violate federal criminal law.” Post, at
18 (opinion of SOTOMAYOR, J.); see post, at 26, 29–30; post,
at 8–9, 10, 12, 16, 20–21 (opinion of JACKSON, J.). The dis-
sents overlook the more likely prospect of an Executive
Branch that cannibalizes itself, with each successive Presi-
dent free to prosecute his predecessors, yet unable to boldly
and fearlessly carry out his duties for fear that he may be
next. For instance, Section 371—which has been charged
in this case—is a broadly worded criminal statute that can
cover “ ‘any conspiracy for the purpose of impairing, ob-
structing or defeating the lawful function of any depart-
ment of Government.’ ” United States v. Johnson, 383 U. S.
169, 172 (1966) (quoting Haas v. Henkel, 216 U. S. 462, 479
(1910)). Virtually every President is criticized for insuffi-
ciently enforcing some aspect of federal law (such as drug,
gun, immigration, or environmental laws). An enterprising
prosecutor in a new administration may assert that a pre-
vious President violated that broad statute. Without im-
munity, such types of prosecutions of ex-Presidents could
quickly become routine. The enfeebling of the Presidency
and our Government that would result from such a cycle of
factional strife is exactly what the Framers intended to
Cite as: 603 U. S. ____ (2024) 41
No. 23–939
_________________
tors “to appoint inferior officers without the advice and con-
sent of the Senate.” NLRB v. SW General, Inc., 580 U. S.
288, 312 (2017) (THOMAS, J., concurring). As relevant here,
a “Hea[d] of Department”—such as the Attorney General—
is one such actor that Congress may authorize “by Law” to
appoint inferior officers without senatorial confirmation.
Art. II, §2, cl. 2.
Before the President or a Department Head can appoint
any officer, however, the Constitution requires that the un-
derlying office be “established by Law.”1 The Constitution
itself creates some offices, most obviously that of the Presi-
dent and Vice President. See §1. Although the Constitution
contemplates that there will be “other Officers of the United
States, whose Appointments are not herein otherwise pro-
vided for,” it clearly requires that those offices “shall be es-
tablished by Law.” §2, cl. 2. And, “established by law” re-
fers to an office that Congress creates “by statute.” Lucia
v. SEC, 585 U. S. 237, 254 (2018) (THOMAS, J., concurring);
see also United States v. Maurice, 26 F. Cas. 1211, 1213
(No. 15,747) (CC Va. 1823) (Marshall, C. J.).
The limitation on the President’s power to create offices
grew out of the Founders’ experience with the English mon-
archy. The King could wield significant power by both cre-
ating and filling offices as he saw fit. He was “emphatically
and truly styled the fountain of honor. He not only ap-
point[ed] to all offices, but [could] create offices.” The Fed-
eralist No. 69, p. 421 (C. Rossiter ed. 1961); see also 1 W.
Blackstone, Commentaries on the Laws of England 271 (T.
——————
1 Although a Government official may also be a “nonofficer employe[e],”
I set aside that category because it is difficult to see how an official exer-
cising the Department of Justice’s duties to enforce the criminal law by
leading a prosecution could be anything but an officer. Lucia v. SEC,
585 U. S. 237, 253, n. 1 (2018) (THOMAS, J., concurring); see SW General,
580 U. S., at 314 (opinion of THOMAS, J.). If the Special Counsel were a
nonofficer employee, the constitutional problems with this prosecution
would only be more serious. For now, I assume without deciding that the
Special Counsel is an officer.
4 TRUMP v. UNITED STATES
Cooley ed. 1871) (“[A]s the king may create new titles, so
may he create new offices”). That ability to create offices
raised many “concerns about the King’s ability to amass too
much power”; the King could both create a multitude of of-
fices and then fill them with his supporters. J. Mascott,
Who Are “Officers of the United States”? 70 Stan. L. Rev.
443, 492 (2018) (Mascott); see also G. Wood, The Creation
of the American Republic 1776–1787, p. 143 (1969) (describ-
ing “the power of appointment to offices” as “the most insid-
ious and powerful weapon of eighteenth-century despot-
ism”); T. Paine, Common Sense (1776), reprinted in The
Great Works of Thomas Paine 11 (1877) (explaining that
“the crown . . . derives its whole consequence merely from
being the giver of places and pensions”). In fact, one of the
grievances raised by the American colonists in declaring
their independence was that the King “ha[d] erected a mul-
titude of New Offices, and sent hither swarms of Officers to
harass our people and eat out their substance.” Declaration
of Independence ¶12. The Founders thus drafted the Con-
stitution with “evidently a great inferiority in the power of
the President, in this particular, to that of the British king.”
The Federalist No. 69, at 421.
The Founders broke from the monarchial model by giving
the President the power to fill offices (with the Senate’s ap-
proval), but not the power to create offices. They did so by
“imposing the constitutional requirement that new officer
positions be ‘established by Law’ rather than through a
King-like custom of the head magistrate unilaterally creat-
ing new offices.” Mascott 492–493 (footnote omitted); see
also 1 Annals of Cong. 581–582 (1789) (“The powers relative
to offices are partly Legislative and partly Executive. The
Legislature creates the office, defines the powers, limits its
duration, and annexes a compensation”); see also ibid. (de-
scribing the power to “designat[e] the man to fill the office”
as “of an Executive nature”). The Constitution thus “giv[es]
Cite as: 603 U. S. ____ (2024) 5
——————
4 Regulations remain on the books that contemplate an “outside” Spe-
cial Counsel, 28 CFR §600.1 (2023), but I doubt a regulation can create a
federal office without underlying statutory authority to do so.
8 TRUMP v. UNITED STATES
No. 23–939
_________________
Court that the supervision and removal of appointed, high ranking Jus-
tice Department officials falls within the President’s core executive
power. See Seila Law LLC v. Consumer Financial Protection Bureau,
591 U. S. 197, 213–215 (2020); ante, at 19–21. I do not understand the
Court to hold that all exercises of the Take Care power fall within the
core executive power. Cf. post, at 24 (SOTOMAYOR, J., dissenting). I agree
with the dissent that the Constitution does not justify such an expansive
view. Ibid.
Cite as: 603 U. S. ____ (2024) 3
——————
2 This analysis is unnecessary for allegations involving the President’s
cuting him for crimes committed when dealing with the Ar-
izona House Speaker would unconstitutionally intrude on
executive power.
This two-step analysis—considering first whether the
statute applies and then whether its application to the par-
ticular facts is constitutional—is similar to the approach
that the Special Counsel presses in this Court. Brief for
United States 24–30. It is also our usual approach to con-
sidering the validity of statutes in situations raising a con-
stitutional question. See, e.g., Seila Law LLC v. Consumer
Financial Protection Bureau, 591 U. S. 197, 213, 229
(2020).3 An important difference in this context is that the
President is entitled to an interlocutory appeal of the trial
court’s ruling. See ante, at 36. A criminal defendant in fed-
eral court normally must wait until after trial to seek re-
view of the trial court’s refusal to dismiss charges. See
United States v. MacDonald, 435 U. S. 850, 853–854 (1978);
see also 18 U. S. C. §3731. But where trial itself threatens
certain constitutional interests, we have treated the trial
court’s resolution of the issue as a “final decision” for pur-
poses of appellate jurisdiction. MacDonald, 435 U. S., at
854–856; see 28 U. S. C. §1291; see also §1257.
——————
3 The Court has sometimes applied an avoidance canon when inter-
* * *
The Constitution does not insulate Presidents from crim-
inal liability for official acts. But any statute regulating the
exercise of executive power is subject to a constitutional
challenge. See, e.g., Collins v. Yellen, 594 U. S. 220, 235–
236 (2021); Zivotofsky v. Clinton, 566 U. S. 189, 192–194
(2012); Free Enterprise Fund v. Public Company Accounting
Oversight Bd., 561 U. S. 477, 487–488 (2010). A criminal
statute is no exception. Thus, a President facing prosecu-
tion may challenge the constitutionality of a criminal stat-
ute as applied to official acts alleged in the indictment. If
that challenge fails, however, he must stand trial.
Cite as: 603 U. S. ____ (2024) 1
No. 23–939
_________________
——————
2 To note, as the majority does, see ante, at 39, that this Court has rec-
C
Our country’s history also points to an established under-
standing, shared by both Presidents and the Justice De-
partment, that former Presidents are answerable to the
criminal law for their official acts. Cf. Chiafalo v. Washing-
ton, 591 U. S. 578, 592–593 (2020) (“ ‘Long settled and es-
tablished practice’ may have ‘great weight in a proper in-
terpretation of constitutional provisions’ ” (quoting The
Pocket Veto Case, 279 U. S. 655, 689 (1929))). Consider Wa-
tergate, for example. After the Watergate tapes revealed
President Nixon’s misuse of official power to obstruct the
Federal Bureau of Investigation’s investigation of the Wa-
tergate burglary, President Ford pardoned Nixon. Both
Ford’s pardon and Nixon’s acceptance of the pardon neces-
sarily “rested on the understanding that the former Presi-
dent faced potential criminal liability.” Brief for United
States 15; see also Public Papers of the Presidents, Gerald
R. Ford, Vol. 1, Sept. 8, 1974, p. 103 (1975) (granting former
President Nixon a “full, free, and absolute pardon . . . for all
offenses against the United States which he . . . has com-
mitted or may have committed or taken part in during” his
Presidency); R. Nixon, Statement by Former President
Richard Nixon to P. Buchen, Counsel to President Ford,
p. 1 (Sept. 8, 1974) (accepting “full and absolute pardon for
any charges which might be brought against me for actions
taken during the time I was President of the United
States”).
Subsequent special counsel and independent counsel in-
vestigations have also operated on the assumption that the
Government can criminally prosecute former Presidents for
their official acts, where they violate the criminal law. See,
e.g., 1 L. Walsh, Final Report of the Independent Counsel
for Iran/Contra Matters: Investigations and Prosecutions
445 (1993) (“[B]ecause a President, and certainly a past
President, is subject to prosecution . . . the conduct of Pres-
10 TRUMP v. UNITED STATES
wise known as private) acts. Even Trump did not claim im-
munity for such acts and, as the majority acknowledges,
such an immunity would be impossible to square with Clin-
ton v. Jones, 520 U. S. 681 (1997). See ante, at 15. This
unremarkable proposition is no real limit on today’s deci-
sion. It does not hide the majority’s embrace of the most
far-reaching view of Presidential immunity on offer.
In fact, the majority’s dividing line between “official” and
“unofficial” conduct narrows the conduct considered “unof-
ficial” almost to a nullity. It says that whenever the Presi-
dent acts in a way that is “ ‘not manifestly or palpably be-
yond [his] authority,’ ” he is taking official action. Ante, at
17 (quoting Blassingame v. Trump, 87 F. 4th 1, 13 (CADC
2023)). It then goes a step further: “In dividing official from
unofficial conduct, courts may not inquire into the Presi-
dent’s motives.” Ante, at 18. It is one thing to say that mo-
tive is irrelevant to questions regarding the scope of civil
liability, but it is quite another to make it irrelevant to
questions regarding criminal liability. Under that rule, any
use of official power for any purpose, even the most corrupt
purpose indicated by objective evidence of the most corrupt
motives and intent, remains official and immune. Under
the majority’s test, if it can be called a test, the category of
Presidential action that can be deemed “unofficial” is des-
tined to be vanishingly small.
Ultimately, the majority pays lip service to the idea that
“[t]he President, charged with enforcing federal criminal
laws, is not above them,” ante, at 13–14, but it then pro-
ceeds to place former Presidents beyond the reach of the
federal criminal laws for any abuse of official power.
B
So how does the majority get to its rule? With text, his-
tory, and established understanding all weighing against it,
the majority claims just one arrow in its quiver: the balanc-
ing test in Nixon v. Fitzgerald, 457 U. S. 731 (1983). Yet
Cite as: 603 U. S. ____ (2024) 13
even that test cuts against it. The majority concludes that
official-acts immunity “is required to safeguard the inde-
pendence and effective functioning of the Executive
Branch,” ante, at 14, by rejecting that Branch’s own protes-
tations that such immunity is not at all required and would
in fact be harmful, see Brief for United States 18–24, 29–
30. In doing so, it decontextualizes Fitzgerald’s language,
ignores important qualifications, and reaches a result that
the Fitzgerald Court never would have countenanced.
In Fitzgerald, plaintiff A. Ernest Fitzgerald sued then-
former President Nixon for money damages. He claimed
that, while in office, Nixon had been involved in unlawfully
firing him from his government job. See 457 U. S., at 733–
741. The question for the Court was whether a former Pres-
ident had immunity from such a civil suit. The Court ex-
plained that it was “settled law that the separation-of-
powers doctrine does not bar every exercise of jurisdiction
over the President of the United States.” Id., at 753–754.
To determine whether a particular type of suit against a
President (or former President) could be heard, a court
“must balance the constitutional weight of the interest to be
served against the dangers of intrusion on the authority
and functions of the Executive Branch.” Id., at 754. The
Court explained that, “[w]hen judicial action is needed to
serve broad public interests—as when the Court acts, not
in derogation of the separation of powers, but to maintain
their proper balance, or to vindicate the public interest in
an ongoing criminal prosecution—the exercise of jurisdic-
tion has been held warranted.” Ibid. (citations omitted).
On the facts before it, the Court concluded that a “merely
private suit for damages based on a President’s official acts”
did not serve those interests. Ibid. The Court reasoned
that the “visibility of [the President’s] office and the effect
of his actions on countless people” made him an easy target
for civil suits that “frequently could distract [him] from his
14 TRUMP v. UNITED STATES
that the majority has created likely will obviate the need to raise them
in future cases. Yet those defenses would have protected former Presi-
dents from unwarranted criminal prosecutions much more precisely
than the blanket immunity the majority creates today.
Cite as: 603 U. S. ____ (2024) 17
C
Finally, in an attempt to put some distance between its
official-acts immunity and Trump’s requested immunity,
the majority insists that “Trump asserts a far broader im-
munity than the limited one [the majority has] recognized.”
Ante, at 32. If anything, the opposite is true. The only part
of Trump’s immunity argument that the majority rejects is
the idea that “the Impeachment Judgment Clause requires
that impeachment and Senate conviction precede a Presi-
dent’s criminal prosecution.” Ibid. That argument is obvi-
ously wrong. See ante, at 32–34. Rejecting it, however,
does not make the majority’s immunity narrower than
Trump’s. Inherent in Trump’s Impeachment Judgment
Clause argument is the idea that a former President who
was impeached in the House and convicted in the Senate
for crimes involving his official acts could then be prose-
cuted in court for those acts. See Brief for Petitioner 22
(“The Founders thus adopted a carefully balanced approach
that permits the criminal prosecution of a former President
for his official acts, but only if that President is first im-
peached by the House and convicted by the Senate”). By
extinguishing that path to overcoming immunity, however
nonsensical it might be, the majority arrives at an official-
acts immunity even more expansive than the one Trump
argued for. On the majority’s view (but not Trump’s), a for-
mer President whose abuse of power was so egregious and
so offensive even to members of his own party that he was
impeached in the House and convicted in the Senate still
would be entitled to “at least presumptive” criminal im-
munity for those acts.
V
Separate from its official-acts immunity, the majority rec-
ognizes absolute immunity for “conduct within [the Presi-
dent’s] exclusive sphere of constitutional authority.” Ante,
at 9. Feel free to skip over those pages of the majority’s
Cite as: 603 U. S. ____ (2024) 23
agrees with it. See ante, at 34. That suggestion will sur-
prise the Government. To say, as the Government did, that
a “small core of exclusive official acts” such as “the pardon
power, the power to recognize foreign nations, the power to
veto legislation, [and] the power to make appointments”
cannot be regulated by Congress, see Tr. of Oral Arg. 85–
87, does not suggest that the Government agrees with im-
munizing any and all conduct conceivably related to the ma-
jority’s broad array of supposedly “core” powers. The Gov-
ernment in fact advised this Court to “leav[e] potentially
more difficult questions” about the scope of any immunity
“that might arise on different facts for decision if they are
ever presented.” Brief for United States 45. That would
have made sense. The indictment here does not pose any
threat of impermissibly criminalizing acts within the Pres-
ident’s “conclusive and preclusive” authority. Perhaps for
this reason, even Trump discouraged consideration of “a
narrower scope of immunity,” claiming that such an im-
munity “would be nearly impossible to fashion, and would
certainly involve impractical line-drawing problems in
every application.” Brief for Petitioner 43–44.
When forced to wade into thorny separation-of-powers
disputes, this Court’s usual practice is to “confine the opin-
ion only to the very questions necessary to decision of the
case.” Dames & Moore v. Regan, 453 U. S. 654, 661 (1981).
There is plenty of peril and little value in crafting a core
immunity doctrine that Trump did not seek and that rightly
has no application to this case.
VI
Not content simply to invent an expansive criminal im-
munity for former Presidents, the majority goes a dramatic
and unprecedented step further. It says that acts for which
the President is immune must be redacted from the narra-
tive of even wholly private crimes committed while in office.
They must play no role in proceedings regarding private
26 TRUMP v. UNITED STATES
——————
5 The majority suggests, in a footnote, that a “prosecutor may point to
the public record to show the fact that the President performed the offi-
cial act,” so long as the prosecutor does not “invite the jury to inspect”
the act in any way. Ante, at 32, n. 3. Whatever that suggestion is sup-
posed to accomplish, it does not salvage the majority’s nonsensical evi-
dentiary rule.
Cite as: 603 U. S. ____ (2024) 27
No. 23–939
_________________
II
A
These foundational presuppositions are reflected in a pro-
cedural paradigm of rules and accountability that operates
in the realm of criminal law—what I would call an individ-
ual accountability model.
The basic contours of that model are familiar, because
they manifest in every criminal case. Criminal law starts
with an act of the legislature, which holds the power “to de-
fine a crime, and ordain its punishment.” United States v.
Wiltberger, 5 Wheat. 76, 95 (1820); accord, Ohio v. Johnson,
467 U. S. 493, 499 (1984). Criminal statutes are laws of
general applicability that express “the assent of the people’s
representatives” that certain conduct is off limits in our so-
ciety. Wooden v. United States, 595 U. S. 360, 391 (2022)
(GORSUCH, J., concurring in judgment).
When the Federal Government believes that someone has
run afoul of a criminal statute and decides to exercise its
prosecutorial discretion to pursue punishment for that vio-
lation, it persuades a grand jury that there is probable
cause to indict. U. S. Const., Amdt. 5. Then, the Govern-
ment marshals evidence to prove beyond a reasonable
doubt that the defendant engaged in the prohibited conduct
and possessed the requisite state of mind. See United
States v. Bailey, 444 U. S. 394, 402 (1980) (observing that,
to hold a person criminally liable, “the concurrence of . . .
‘an evil-meaning mind [and] an evil-doing hand’ ” must be
proved (quoting Morissette v. United States, 342 U. S. 246,
251 (1952))).
For his part, the defendant “stands accused but is pre-
sumed innocent until conviction upon trial or guilty plea.”
Betterman v. Montana, 578 U. S. 437, 441 (2016). Notably,
criminal defendants have various constitutionally pro-
tected rights during the criminal-liability process, includ-
ing the rights to a speedy and public trial, the right to have
a jury decide guilt or innocence, the right to the assistance
4 TRUMP v. UNITED STATES
——————
1 See R. Perkins & R. Boyce, Criminal Law 1093 (3d ed. 1982) (“Deeds
——————
3 It is important to note that the majority reframes the immunity ques-
digm works slightly differently; she would have us ask, first, “whether
the relevant criminal statute reaches the President’s official conduct.”
Ante, at 2. But, again, what is at issue here are statutes of general ap-
plicability—they only “reach” the President’s conduct to the extent that
he chooses to engage in the prohibited behavior. See n. 3, supra. JUSTICE
BARRETT’s framing, thus, sidesteps the fact that, when immunity is being
considered, what is actually at issue is whether the President is exempt
from punishment if he opts to exercise his official duties using means
that violate criminal law.
Cite as: 603 U. S. ____ (2024) 9
cuse; the law simply does not apply to him. Unlike a de-
fendant who invokes an affirmative defense and relies on a
legal determination that there was a good reason for his
otherwise unlawful conduct, a former President invoking
immunity relies on the premise that he can do whatever he
wants, however he wants, so long as he uses his “ ‘official
power’ ” in doing so. Ante, at 19. In the former paradigm,
the President remains subject to law; in the latter, he is
above it.
III
JUSTICE SOTOMAYOR has already warned of the dire con-
sequences that are likely to follow from the majority’s deci-
sion in this case. Ante, at 29–30 (dissenting opinion). I have
thus far endeavored merely to explain what today’s ruling
amounts to on a theoretical level: the Court’s abandonment
of the individual accountability model as applied to Presi-
dents, and its introduction of a new Presidential accounta-
bility model that authorizes the Judiciary to exempt Presi-
dents from punishment under law, depending on the official
or unofficial character of the criminal conduct at issue.
Here, I will highlight just two observations about the re-
sults that follow from this paradigm shift. First, by chang-
ing the accountability paradigm in this fashion, the Court
has unilaterally altered the balance of power between the
three coordinate branches of our Government as it relates
to the Rule of Law, aggrandizing power in the Judiciary and
the Executive, to the detriment of Congress. Second, the
majority’s new Presidential accountability model under-
mines the constraints of the law as a deterrent for future
Presidents who might otherwise abuse their power, to the
detriment of us all.
A
Consider the structural implications of today’s decision
from the standpoint of the separation of powers. Until now,
Cite as: 603 U. S. ____ (2024) 13
——————
6 Some of the powers the majority designates as “core” powers are, at
——————
7 See, e.g., Plato, Laws 274 (B. Jowett transl. 2000) (“Not that he is
punished because he did wrong, for that which is done can never be un-
done, but in order that in future times, he, and those who see him cor-
rected, may utterly hate injustice, or at any rate abate much of their evil-
doing”); see also J. Bentham, The Rationale of Punishment 20 (1830)
(“General prevention ought to be the chief end of punishment, as it is its
real justification”); A. von Hirsch, Doing Justice: The Choice of Punish-
ments 44 (1976) (“The threat and imposition of punishment is called for
in order to secure compliance—not full compliance, but more compliance
than there might be were there no legal penalties at all”).
8 See, e.g., M. Ryan, Taking Another Look at Second-Look Sentencing,
any American who has studied history knows that “our gov-
ernment was designed to have such restrictions.” Ibid. (em-
phasis added). Our Constitution’s “separation of powers
was adopted by the Convention of 1787, not to promote ef-
ficiency but to preclude the exercise of arbitrary power. The
purpose was, not to avoid friction, but . . . to save the people
from autocracy.” Myers v. United States, 272 U. S. 52, 293
(1926) (Brandeis, J., dissenting).
Having now cast the shadow of doubt over when—if
ever—a former President will be subject to criminal liability
for any criminal conduct he engages in while on duty, the
majority incentivizes all future Presidents to cross the line
of criminality while in office, knowing that unless they act
“manifestly or palpably beyond [their] authority,” ante, at
17, they will be presumed above prosecution and punish-
ment alike.
But the majority also tells us not to worry, because “[l]ike
everyone else, the President is subject to prosecution in his
unofficial capacity.” Ante, at 40 (emphasis added). This at-
tempted reassurance is cold comfort, even setting aside the
fact that the Court has neglected to lay out a standard that
reliably distinguishes between a President’s official and un-
official conduct. Why? Because there is still manifest ineq-
uity: Presidents alone are now free to commit crimes when
they are on the job, while all other Americans must follow
the law in all aspects of their lives, whether personal or pro-
fessional. The official-versus-unofficial act distinction also
seems both arbitrary and irrational, for it suggests that the
unofficial criminal acts of a President are the only ones wor-
thy of prosecution. Quite to the contrary, it is when the
President commits crimes using his unparalleled official
powers that the risks of abuse and autocracy will be most
dire. So, the fact that, “unlike anyone else, the President
is” vested with “sweeping powers and duties,” ibid., actually
underscores, rather than undermines, the grim stakes of
setting the criminal law to the side when the President
20 TRUMP v. UNITED STATES